Editor�s
Note: I
wrote the article
�Ideology, Class Struggle, And Ethiopian Politics� ten years
ago at a time when the fate of Ethiopia was in the balance.
(Originally, it was published in Ethiopian Review, in
1996.) What I wrote to be truly crucial then is even truer at this
time ten years later. Some times to get the attention of my
students and to their deep puzzlement, I challenge them to give me
as an example a more �socialist� nation in the world than the
United States. The United States is a nation that has more
regulations and regulatory agencies, as well as numerous voluntary
establishments, than any nation in the world. Even the United
States Supreme Court in its very recent decision in Kelo
v. City of New London, opted in favor of
communal interest above private property interest. If that is not
a socialist ideology at work, tell me what is. We are posting this
article with very slight changes herein because of its timeless
truth and relevance to our situation in 2005. TH
IDEOLOGY,
CLASS STRUGGLE, AND ETHIOPIAN POLITICS
By Tecola W. Hagos
[December 1996/
slightly modified on June 25, 2005]
I. Ideology and
Change: �Socialism� is not Dead
It might be helpful (for my analysis of the ongoing political
struggle in Ethiopia) to bring some perspective on the role of
ideology in Ethiopian political structures. It is during the
government of Mengistu that for the first time in Ethiopian history
a government was instituted pursuant to an ideology. Before that,
almost all Ethiopian governments were traditional power structures
born out of (then) existing social systems. The few exceptions to
this fact might be the case of Gragn Mohammed in the 16th Century,
where Islamic religion provided a political ideology that was
deliberately instituted; and later in the 17th Century the attempted
introduction of Catholicism by Emperor Susneyos might qualify as
another attempt at changing existing traditional political
structures pursuant to an ideology. Thus, efforts of most Ethiopian
liberation movements at the present time need be seen as a positive
development to replace the tradition of personalized state power by
structuring political power in adherence to an ideology.
At this point, it will be a grave mistake for anyone to
conclude that socialist ideas are obsolete and the communist
world-view is dead and buried because of the collapse of the Soviet
Union in the late 1980s. Consider this fact, as expressed by Ralph
Nader in one of his Presidential candidature addresses (at Stanford
University, October 1996), that a mere three hundred eighty (380)
individuals control as much wealth owned by three billion people of
the world (counted from the bottom up)! This is a world where
billions of dollars is spent to feed pets whereas millions of
children are starving and dying in appalling conditions. Living in a
world of such extreme cases of greed and poverty as well as
frivolity, who can say in his right mind that we are living in an
equitable and just world and remain satisfied with the status quo?
Francis Fukuyama, as a too eager modern days Cassandra or
Pollyanna depending on your trajectory, penned in his book, The
End of History and the Last Man, a book expanded from an article
by the same title written in 1989, wherein he declared that Western
liberal democracy has won and that is the �end of history,� and
everything else after is mere elaboration and semantics. In other
words, we are living in the watershed of history, that there can be
no new or creative political engagement nor the possibility of
meaningful epoch-making change.
Fukuyama's glossy capitalist world-view at its core equates
socialist change with the Soviet Union, and the demise of the Soviet
Union to be empirical evidence that socialism does not work. Of
course, such reasoning is based on two false premises: a) the Soviet
Union was a socialist state, and b) the demise of a single state
structure is a conclusive proof that socialism is a failure as a
political and economic system. The existentialist philosopher,
Sartre, a well informed critic of Marxism and a far more enlightened
intellectual than the novice Fukuyama, perceived of the end of
history as the coming of age of �ethics� (Jean-Paul Sartre, Cahiers
pour une morale, 1983) and not the triumph of the philosophy of
greed and laissez-faire. And even that in the indefinite future, no
where close to our time or Century. At any rate, Schweickart in his
monumental book (David Schweickart, Against Capitalism, 1996)
has refuted such premature hooray on the alleged triumph of
capitalism and the demise of socialism (communism). Even more
important, Schweickart has provided us with an alternative socialist
model of economic and political structure that deserves our
attention.
The struggle of oppressed and disfranchised people of the
world did not die with the demise of the Soviet Union. In as much as
the Soviet Union never truly addressed the political empowerment of
workers in its heyday, it will not derail the course of history with
its new found love affair with capitalism nor would it deter workers
from struggling for their rights elsewhere in the world. The fact
remains that Cuba and China are still with us. The Soviet Union was
never a champion of the working person, and as a matter of record,
the only time there ever existed a government run directly by
workers was during the few months the Bolsheviks were in power
before they were destroyed by Lenin and his collaborators. The
immense value of the Soviet Union was not for its democratic
institutions or the promotion of the economic and political power of
workers, but for its symbolism and deterrence of the capitalist West
from overrunning the world at a time when the world was too backward
and uninitiated. On the other side of the scale, the value of the
United States was not for its stand for equity or justice, nor for
freedom or equality but for its usefulness as a counterweight
against immediate annihilation of minority groups and as a place for
temporary refuge from persecution by despotic regimes.
What we are observing in the last two decades of the
Second Millennium is not the advancement of liberal democracy but
rather the breakdown of civil society everywhere: a deterioration of
social responsibility, and the surge of individualism and ethnicity.
Both are expressions of negative primordial and primitive urges; the
first focusing on the individual's primitive acquisitive nature, and
the second on how such individual form anti-social groups in tandem
with others and how they relate to such groups. This
deterioration is not limited to the Soviet Union, but is also a
fundamental aspect of the reality of Western societies. For example,
the United States is going through political and racial fracture
with no solution insight, and the end of which would be most
disastrous as symbolically expressed in the Oklahoma bombing, on one
hand, and a series of anti-people laws issued by the Congress and
imperialist policy pursued by the Executive, on the other side. And
After 9/11 terrorist attack, the erosion of democratic and human
rights with the enactment of The PATRIOT Act is a clear example how
far the United States has compromised human rights. The Abu Gharib
and Guantanamo Bay Prisons of torture and abuse are clear examples
of the corruption of �capitalism� at its worst.
The recent diplomatic effort of the U.S. government to create
a rapid deployment force to be used as an intrastate enforcer of
peace and stability in Africa is no different from the establishment
of a mercenary army aimed at quelling all future revolutions in
African nations. This is a time when liberalism is considered to be
a dirty concept. The resurgence of Nazism in Germany and fascistic
tendencies in Italy, France and Britain all point to the fact that
the problem is pervasive and world wide. This world wide phenomenon
of excessive xenophobia, unrest and greed might even be the calling
(warning) card of the Third Millennium and necessarily a harbinger
of future world disasters. In Ethiopia, they have succeeded to train
and equip a mercenary force called Age�azi that resembles more
like the Tom-Tom-Macoute of Papa-Doc Duvalier of Haiti.
Whether we call it class struggle or aggregation of
individualized struggle for political and economic power, such
grouping by interest is a human social reality and not some flimsy
semantic or word association or construction. Through out history,
people have formed groups, pulled by common interest, and have
sought protection by being a member of such a group. It will be
naive for any one to deny such reality when the evidence is clearly
laid out in front of our eyes. Even in the animal world, we see such
primordial groupings of a class of predators and a class of preys.
What distinguishes the human class aggregation from that of animals
is the deliberate nature of the class groupings of the human actors.
Although this statement might be seen as a proposition that confused
animal instinct with human nature, at any rate the point is made. In
an essay of this nature, I will not attempt to reiterate the
conceptualization of this reality to the same degree and
thoroughness and elaboration by Marx or other philosophers of
materialism.
However, on a far more fundamental level, even class interest
alone cannot explain adequately the existence of groups. Throughout
human history, some groups, although small in number, had welded
disproportional economic and political power over a vast underclass.
In order to understand the dynamic of power-groups, I believe we
have to dig deeper into the recesses of human beginning to have an
understanding of the dynamic forces that shaped societies and made
civilization possible. It seems to me that it might have to do with
two conflicting interests: a) the male urge to have access to mate
with as many females as possible and to propagate issues, and
b) the female, as the key of life, wanting to insure the best
possible male to father her children. Each had developed unique
strategies, and society, as we know it is the result. The female
represent tremendous internal personal investment in this drama of
life; whereas the investment of the male is on the outside on social
power structure. That is why it is a fact that biology is far more
entrenched than sociology. Freud alluded, in his books Civilization
and Its Discontent and Three Essays on Sexuality
to this same basic sex based explanation of the deformities of all
cultures due to the frustration or unfulfillment of sexual desires
(the Oedipus and Electra complexes) of the individual. While both
Marx and Sartre identified culture as repressive, they did so basing
their conclusions on sociological and economic reasons, a positivist
manner of reasoning, i.e., from society to the individual.
In fact, it is within such understanding of basic human urges
and frustrations that one can speak of human nature. Although the
labeling of certain actions or behavior as a question of human
nature is a highly contested issue, recent scientific postulates
suggest that there might be certain and identifiable characteristics
of human nature shared by all human beings. One may see this as the
initial wiring of the brain. How else can we explain the basic
similarity of grammatical structure common to all languages? (Noam
Chomsky, Syntactic Structures, 1957; Current Issues in
Linguistic Theory, 1964) Or the recognition associated with the
concept of the self in all human beings? Or fear and anxiety? Or
altruism? Of course, this is not the same as claiming inherent
normative (moral) nature. However, there seems to be a strong case
supporting the existence of some form of a shared human moral nature
which has much deeper origin than being a result of a mere
consequence of sexual repression or frustration.
For example, by contrast, Sartre frontally rejected the
concept of human nature. He saw human beings sharing in a general
human "condition" and acting or reacting individually in
that condition and not having a pre-ordained "nature"
(Jean-Paul Sartre, Reflexions sur la question juive, Anti-Semite
and Jew, 1968; Cahiers pour une morale, 1983; Critique
of Dialectical Reason, 1976). This idea of being in a common
"condition" is far from sharing in a "nature"
(taking the common meaning of the word). One might argue that
Sartre's approach might completely undermine the idea of free
will and the human creative dimension since according to such views
human (re)action becomes wholly dependent on external events.
Sartre's problem seems to be a misreading of the human positive
response, which is proactive from the one that is part of history
that is either reactive or reflective. It seems to me that both
"nature" and "condition" may explain aspects of
individual lives and human history, thus the (Sartrean) dichotomy or
the Marxist exclusive and tight understanding of history may not be
necessary or proper.
As members of the human family, Ethiopians too suffered
similar fracturing and preemptive social disassembly as the rest of
the world (humankind). It is only within that world-context of the
larger community of diverse peoples of the world that we could be
able to make sense of our peculiar problems. If we lose sight of
such world perspective, we will start thinking that our pedantic
problems are world-shaking problems and start mistaking the anthills
of our discontent for mountains of insurmountable adversities. We
are not unique in our suffering of injustice, deprivation and
exploitation in a desperate neck and neck struggle with an
exploitative class represented by all formal structures of
suppression and oppressors called governments (with an obvious
degree of irony). To argue the relative importance of such
conceptual trajectory is one thing, but to deny outright the
legitimacy of such an explanation or description of social reality
amounts to burying ones head in the sands of history like an Ostrich
faced with the reality of its mortality.
Could anyone explain to me why leaders of a liberation
movement, the TPLF/EPRDF that had struggled against one of the
world's worst dictatorial governments for almost two decades, take
into their wings entrenched officials who had served Haile Selassie
and the now defunct military government of Mengistu, if it were not
for class interest? Or was it necessary to seek out the sons and
daughters of past feudal masters in diverse ethnic groups around the
country to establish satellite fronts. It is not blood that binds
but class interest, which creates strange bedfellows. Meles who
thinks with an arrogant sense of infallibility that he is in control
of the different forces in play in Ethiopia, is in reality a clay
being molded and manipulated by the entrenched Ethiopian bureaucrats
and rich merchant class who had successfully infiltrated and
survived every Ethiopian government that had come into power in the
last one hundred years. Like all Ethiopian dictators before him, he
too has failed as a revolutionary leader, and his leadership has
decomposed into a self-dealing ethnocracy and oligarchy.
In general, there are three objections to the idea of the
existence of classes in society that are in perpetual antagonistic
relationships: 1) pre-industrial societies did not have clear
dichotomy of classes; however, conflicts were prevalent during such
periods; 2) the idea of class conflict is deterministic and does not
acknowledge the individualized initiatives of specific events and
actions taken by individuals throughout history; and 3) that it is a
simplistic formulation of a very complex socio-political and
economic process and favors without adequate basis the idea of group
evolutionary selection. I believe that these objections, though
valid as observations on the general human condition, could not
qualify as legitimate criticisms of Marxism because such objections
seem to confuse methods of understanding of events in history with
suggestions of solutions to economic and political problems. Marxism
deals with both method of understanding of current situation through
its history and also provides solutions based on objective and
scientific synthesis of the experience of society.
II. Against
Ethnicism: Delaminating the �Self� from the �Selfish,�
Altruism as Socialism
The first ideology based solution to the age-old economic and
political problems of Ethiopia came in the form of a coup d'etat
attempted by some elite military leaders in the 1960s. Of course,
there were numerous challenges to Ethiopian despots in the past.
However, those early challenges, prior to the 1960s, were usually
attempts to acquire power rather than an attempt to change the
political structure of the nation. The military takeover in the
1970s was an attempt to make a clear jump from the traditional power
structure of Ethiopia, which was based on the beliefs and
circumstances of medieval mentality, right over the periods of
mercantile and industrial transformations to that of a Twentieth
Century Marxist ideology. It was more of a leap of faith than
scientific.
On questions of political and economic ideology, especially
on issues of liberation movements and nationalism, I can surmise my
thought in one simple sentence: all are means to an end, and their
value is rooted not in their immutable truth but in their relation
to the type of results that can be achieved through them.
Nationalism is based on primitive and primordial impulse of the need
for group formation. I do not think of the concept of nationalism,
especially the one that is narrowly defined, as a particularly
enlightened one. Narrow nationalism may be synonymous with ethnicism,
which has no place, in my view, in any political processes
especially in a country like Ethiopia. I admit that in the past I
have written about the more inclusive idea of nationalism with some
emphasis. I still believe that nationalism has a constructive role
to play in the construction of the modern cosmopolitan man and as a
process of liberation, and not as an end goal. This view maybe
misunderstood easily and could be mistaken as a support for narrow
nationalism or ethnicism. Even though nationalism is in my view the
lower part of the ladder of civilization, we cannot be able to climb
up to enlightened society without the support of those lower steps.
Ultimately, even boundaries between states cannot be justified if
one is honest enough to see the humanity of the one in all other
human beings and the superficiality of national boundaries become
very obvious.
I believe that a group led by a democratic liberation
movement with the right formulation of an economic and political
ideology, with a good sense of nationalistic identification, might
advance the development of a "national" economic and
socialist political system. In fact, this is tautological, and
almost no one can disagree with such a blanket statement. The
problem arises on questions of methods, and on how fast to get
there. There are as many diverse approaches as individuals and their
political views. There are many roads that can take us to Addis
Ababa. Socialism is one such a road, and in my view the best yet to
be realized. However, the road being taken by the present Ethiopian
government definitely will not work. The Ethiopian government on the
economic front has attracted mostly profiteers and carpetbaggers;
and on the political front, the government of Meles seems to be
mainly interested in its own power hegemony and has become
increasingly alienated from the Ethiopian public.
In the past and in our own time, there have been innumerable
arguments against socialist mode of economic and political
structures. In fact, famous scholars like Hayek had outright
asserted that socialism "is the road to serfdom" (F.A.
Hayek, The Road to Serfdom, 1944). Even a left leaning famous
economist of our own time, Robert Heilbroner, conceded in 1989 that
the contest between capitalism and socialism was over and capitalism
had won. (Robert Heilbroner, "The Triumph of Capitalism," New
Yorker, January, 1989; David Schweickart, Against Capitalism,
1996) These criticisms of socialism or concessions are all
existential conclusions or understandable personal reactions to a
dramatic moment in history (in case of Hayek, Nazism and World War
II; and in case of Heilbroner, the unexpected collapse of the Soviet
Union) and do not in any formal and empirical manner conclusively
disprove the positive claims of socialist thinkers.
The fact remains that capitalism is a very wasteful system,
and ultimately doomed to self-destruction. Capitalism is a system
built on a negative worldview, a world, the poet Alfred Lord
Tennyson described, lamenting the death of a dear friend in his poem
�In Memoriam,� as "Nature red in tooth and claw."
There can be no peaceful future in a world where less than 5% of the
world's population controls 90% of the world's wealth. In a world
where billions of people are living under appalling conditions,
change cannot be on a piecemeal basis and gradual. And closer to
home, the economic and political condition in Ethiopia, with over
50% unemployment rate and with the lowest per capita income in the
world, is illustrative of a sick world. Thus, change has to be swift
and drastic. And revolution is the proper and inevitable method to
effect such change in the type of world we have at this point.
Revolutionary change does not necessarily involve violent methods.
There is no strong argument against a fair distribution of
the resources of a society among those who produced those resources.
The question becomes more confusing as we try to see the mechanism
for such distribution. Distribution includes not only the
distribution of resources, but also duties to society. In order to
make some sense of all social interactions, we must assume that
society is ultimately a consensual endeavor. Whether such consent is
perceived to be a constructed or an actual one, the fact remains
that in numerous instances individuals act in manners those
societies would expect them to act even where there are no
supervisors or overseers. It is in the best interest of the
individual to live within society and abide by the rules of such a
society. The relationship between the individual and society seems
to be asymmetrical in the sense that the individual benefits from
his relationship in society more than society would have lost
because of the individual's nonparticipation.
For years, the idea that evolution favored a selfish
individual over an altruistic one had given strength to the argument
in support of capitalist or laissez faire economic systems (George
C. Williams, Adaptation and Natural Selection, 1966; Richard
Dawkins, The Selfish Gene, 1976). On the other hand, there are
studies that confirm the fact that communal or collectivist social
structures are the natural state of human existence and society. The
social Darwinists (which ironically included both extremes from the
capitalist and communist camps) from the Nineteenth Century to date
had misrepresented Charles Darwin's ideas on the struggle for
survival and natural selection. Either they supported the idea of an
open-ended social and economic struggle without any innate
restraint, or they saw life caught in a relentless deterministic
process. Darwin and many evolutionist scientists saw group
selection/altruism as a fundamental biological evolutionary process.
Darwin wrote, at the very outset of his scientific inquiry into
life, "I use the term struggle for existence in a large and
metaphorical sense, including dependence of one being on
another." [Charles Darwin, On the Origin of Species by Means
of Natural Selection or the Preservation of Favored Races in the
Struggle for Life, 1859; The Decent of Man and Selection in
Relation to Sex, 1871] Developing this theme further, Kropotkin
acknowledged the collectivist idea of cooperation to be far more in
tune with the natural world than the antagonistic and
confrontational world picture of Marxism. [Petr Kropotkin, Mutual
Aid: A Factor of Evolution, Dover, 1929]
Recently,
even the Pope is reported to have acknowledged the fact that
theories of evolution are more than mere hypothesis. In other words,
group selection is an evolutionary reality, which is a favored
natural condition as opposed to narrow individualism. How else can
we explain the chastity of the Catholic Church's priesthood or those
of monks of different religions if not for altruism and group
selection. This view is not some fanciful stretching of the mind.
There are individuals who had devoted a life time of rigorous study
on this same issue whose finding support altruism and the theory of
evolutionary group selection. David S. Wilson and Elliot R. Sober
had written extensively for the last twenty years on the question of
group selection and/or altruism, and their book, Unto Others: The
Evolution and Psychology of Unselfish behavior, Harvard, 1998.
The famous biologist E. O. Wilson said, �Unto 0thers is an
important, original, and well-written book. It contains the
definitive contemporary statement on higher-level selection and the
evolutionary origin of cooperation.�
And to those who are more reflective and ambivalent about
either school of thought, Helena Cronin might provide some solace
(Helena Cronin, The Ant and the Peacock, 1991). However, one
must be aware also of the danger of a too rigid interpretation of
the concept of group selection at its worst it could be used as a
devastating racist tool. I have discussed this problem extensively
in my essay "Altruism and the Social Contract."
The pinnacle (achievement) of capitalism is the corporation, an
artificial legal creation with most of the privileges and rights of
real human individuals, but with none of the inconvenience and pain
of real human existence, a perfect machine of anti-democratic and
dictatorial system of control and exploitation. The corporation
cannot be subjected to the evolutionary
process of life. Thus, it remains outside of the natural progression
of life, nevertheless anomalous to all human progress without it
being affected in turn.
Moreover, concepts of private property and individualized
ownership of land (natural resources) are recent developments. Even
in the most entrenched capitalist countries, residual collectivist
or communist practices are still in existence preserved in concepts
like "public domain," "international waters,"
"wild life," "nature," et cetera. The concept of
laissez-faire even where it is coupled with the idea of competition
(a far more natural behavior) does not have the type of scientific
basis in society as does collectivism or communism. For example, the
concept of inheritance, the crown jewel of laissez-faire societies,
has absolutely no basis in early human societies. Even in the modern
capitalist societies its validity is questionable, the very high tax
rates on inherited property, in almost all Western countries,
confirms this observation.
The chronic problem of underdevelopment in countries like
Ethiopia is compounded because of ethnic conflict and a tradition of
despotic political structures. It does not take much to prove that
traditional methods of government and despotic human relations have
not worked well in Ethiopia. At the present time, Ethiopia, a
country with tremendous natural resources and centuries of
independent existence, is considered to be the poorest nation on
Earth. It has become a wasteland of unimaginable suffering. How else
can we explain this obvious contradiction between existing
conditions of stark poverty against the potential for real
development other than by the fact of centuries of bad government
and horrible personal relations. Until recently, Ethiopians were
identified as "subjects" (see Haile Selassie's 1955
Revised Constitution of Ethiopia, Preamble and Articles 45, 47,
49-50, 64, 95-96, 103) in an aristocratic government structure.
Moreover, it was only in 1987 that Ethiopians were formally
acknowledged as �citizens� by the ruling body under Mengistu's
Constitution. Thus, not all traditional political structures that
had ever existed in Ethiopia had been beneficial to the majority of
Ethiopians.
Ethiopian culture continued to be a negative factor in the
political life of even the expatriate Ethiopian population in the
United State. The Ethiopian expatriate elite in general remains
antidemocratic, unaffected even after several decades of exposure to
the infectious Americanism engulfing us all. Some may see this
insolubility as a laudable characteristic of an ancient culture,
while others consider it as a point of scorn and ridicule. The
Ethiopian elite is forced to fight on two fronts at the same time:
a) a relentless fight to preserve a certain identity against the
tremendous pull into oblivion within a socially disadvantaged group
of people of color and the fear of being submerged in a sea of
nothingness in foreign nations; and b) the competitive fight to
preserve within the Ethiopian community traditionally sanctified
positions of respect and importance, where the struggle looks to me
pitifully anachronistic.
Africa does not seem to have much future in the next few
decades or beyond. Although a group of distinguished intellectuals
from the West and Africa, meeting at a workshop in Kenya in 1987,
had concluded that Africa has a bright future in the 21st
Century, I believe that such conclusion was more of a leap of faith
than the dictate of hard data. African national governments and
their economic structures seem to have nothing to do with the modern
world economic or political systems; Africans seem to survive as
marginalized people and fodder to other human groups. This is an
obvious overstatement with a kernel of an ugly truth that Africans
are on the way to extinction unless they effect a radical turn of
events. In a recently published book, Robert Kaplan wrote about the
grim reality he observed in his travels through a number of African
nations (Robert D. Kaplan, The Ends of the Earth: A Journey at
the Dawn of the 21st Century, 1996). Although Kaplan wrote about
the bright Eritrean future as an exception to the general doom
Africa is faced with, he did not visit Ethiopia. It may not be that
wise to take Kaplan's conclusions without some reservation. After
all, Kaplan seems to be a gleeful amateur who is an interested party
in the demise of African people or of their descendants elsewhere.
However, we must take note of the basis of his analysis as an
additional evidence of a looming African disaster, and take
appropriate remedial steps to avert that danger.
The ultimate question facing each one of us, in the final
analysis, after everything has been said and done, is the issue of
our individual mortality. To paraphrase Dostoyevsky, the prospect of
an immediate death concentrates the mind. With my own mortality in
view, such concentration of mind is inevitable; things and events
fall into perspective giving me a far more honest insight into the
reality of my own existence and life in general. Thus, let me put it
as plainly as I could as follows: There is no reason for me to step
aside to let "You" and your issue pass to my detriment
(unless it is to the benefit of society). That is precisely what is
being demanded of us by a minuscule number of individuals who are
illegally in power and fraudulently in control of the means of
production of society and the products of our labor, and even of our
spirit. As far as I was able to ascertain, there is only one
immutable truth, i.e., the need of the many is at least as
important, if not more, as the need of the individual. END
Tecola W. Hagos
December 1996, slightly modified on June 25,
2005
|