FINAL INSTALLMENT
CIVIL DISOBEDIENCE, TRUTH, AND HUMAN RIGHTS
By Tecola W.
Hagos
PART TWO: TRUTH AND HUMAN RIGHTS
Section II: Theories of Verification and
Truth
�To
see a World in a Grain of Sand
And a Heaven in a Wild Flower,
Hold Infinity in the palm of your hand
And Eternity in an hour.�
From �Auguries of Innocence� by William Blake
Introduction
In this part of
my essay, I have departed considerably from my usual preference of analytical (not deconstruction) writing; I am more inclined
toward synthesis in this piece of writing.[1] There is no question
that the first safest approach to solving a problem is to
compartmentalize or break the problem down to its basic structure
thereby making it manageable. Issues dealing with truth and human
rights, probably due to the nature of the subject matter, might
necessitate synthesis as the better illuminating approach more than
analysis. To a great extent, I must confess, that I mustered some
courage to present this article after having read a small but
dynamite book by an Oxford University philosopher Flipe Fernandez-Armesto,
Truth: A Guide for the
Perplexed (Black Swan, 1998).[2] If perplexity is a measure
of inadequacy, then I am the most perplexed person about life in
general and Ethiopia�s future in particular.
There is much
that is extremely complex about the subject of human rights, a
subject matter that I spent studying, debating, analyzing et cetera
most of my adult life. At one point in my search, I went through a
phase whereby I adopted the structuralist understanding of human
rights. It was a passing phase, and a kind of throw-back antithesis
to my early (HSIU years) attraction to existentialism, a philosophy
that answered to my basic needs of the time of the possibility of
absolute freedom in an absurd universe�a core philosophical school
providing answers to a young man asking investigatory questions
about life for the first time. It is later through my close
examination of Parmenides and Plato/Socrates that I came to realize
that the connection between �truth� and �human rights� has
an ontological aspect as profound as any other adventure of the
mind. Transcendental and universalized concepts have became
overwhelmingly persuasive to my mind. Thus, my argument that human
rights principles are universal principles has its own tortured
evolution.
I have tried to
answer basic questions of human rights dealing with minorities and
ethnic groups in light of the universality of human rights. I have
dealt with the contentious principle of self-determination at its
basic formulation in order to provide my readers a coherent picture
of human rights as universal principles. Too often, our voice is a
voice in the wilderness when we challenge minorities and ethnic
groups demanding special considerations that effectively breach the
peaceful coexistence of the many constituents of the whole. In an
attempt to show how the principles of human rights are universal
principles cutting across the entire human spectrum let alone one
country, I have also addressed the misapplication of principles of
self-determination that has spawned a number of �liberation
movements� in Ethiopia. I have included pertinent citations at the
end of this article that would be a good starting point for more
extensive research. There
is no need to be a toothless lion roaring in the wilderness as ye
gedel mamito, for I believe I have moral, legal, historical, and
cultural justification for insisting for a unitary state of Ethiopia
and the respect and safeguard of human rights.
1) Beware of History Repeating Itself and
Corrupting the �Truth�
Most of our
political disagreements revolve around claims dealing with
legitimacy of political power, economic benefits, cultural identity,
and nationalism. Much of such conflicts would have been avoided by
simple acknowledgement of a common understanding of how to verify
assertions of truth in cases of disputed claims and conflicts, in
our general social interactions.
Of course, the search for truth and even finding such truth
is no defense against an immediate destruction perpetrated by the
single-minded selfish pursuit of individuals organized as a group.
No society is ever free from �barbarians.� In every
society the world over, there are individuals that truly are the
scourge of social and cultural developments. It is in society�s
fight against such destructive forces that society also achieves a
degree of enlightenment. Am I being deterministic or fateful? To a
limited extent, the answer could only be �yes,� however, it
would be a mistake to frame a thesis based on such limited scope.
My statements
(above) are grandiose overgeneralizations, but I rather err on the
side of overemphasis and overgeneralization as such than walk
cautiously with minced ideas that will not be sufficient to display
the splendor of Ethiopia. In the effort to understand our particular
history, I had ventured out challenging very many myths and taboo
subjects for Ethiopians to discuss. I have been vilified by
individuals who hid behind fake names in chat groups and the like,
but never challenged properly on any of my research and analysis
except once by an individual I do not want to mention here since he
has completely disappeared from the ongoing discourse on Ethiopia. I
seek truth, for truth is not mere matching of events to perception
or the pedantic matching of witnesses to such events. I believe the
very search for truth is a positive act. In fact, I may even
consider it as an act of worship. In fact, it was in Eighth Grade
that I realized �truth� is something very special as I tug along
reading the book by Sir H. Ridder Haggard, She,
where �Truth� was worshiped.
The modern world
is far more complex than a young boy would ever comprehend. Thus,
the concept of truth has become also far more complex than mere
statue to be worshiped by people in loincloths. It is in this sense
of intense complexity that I am discussing the concept and reality
of �truth� and verification not just as a subject of speculation
and intellectual indulgence. If we take as an example of the
disembodied identity and scope of what Ethiopian reality signifies
to individuals who are far removed from Ethiopia in all measurements
of proximity, we will be able to measure our own distance from the
reality of Ethiopia, This is a sort of sociological/cultural cum
political triangulation. It is amazing how much our understanding of
our Ethiopian reality contrasts with the cursory and often corrupted
perceptions foreigners have of Ethiopia and Ethiopians.
One can make a
defensible case for the cyclical nature of history. Even though this
may be a contradiction to my objection to the deterministic
perception of human life, there is enough latitude within such
organic structure that may not be as deterministic as it might look.
In other words, our judgment of history is always after the
fact, a reflective one and does not in any rational manner establish
the deterministic nature of human life. Having said that, it is
alarming to see the monster of Red Terror rearing its head
camouflaging itself as part of the opposition movement to the
current Ethiopian Government. Yesterdays supporters and defenders of
Mengistu�s brutal government that had caused for over seventeen
years untold atrocities with tens of thousands of murders and
disappearances, are now reinventing themselves by associating with
the few honorable men and women of the leadership of the Opposition.
Even though it is delayed justice, the recent conviction of Melaku
Tefera for crimes of genocide and crime against humanity, represent
the tip of the iceberg of barbarism and Red Terror violence of the
seventeen years rule of Mengistu and his collaborators. Like Melaku
Tefera, also known as the butcher of Gondar, there are thousands
others still at large, and even some well established within the
Diaspora communities of Ethiopians.
We have
individuals who were serving Mengistu as junior and senior
diplomats, high-ranking officials, privileged businessmen, et cetera
now waving the banner of the Opposition and putting themselves
beyond criticism and accountability. Such enablers of Mengistu and
his brutal government for almost two decades are now dressed in new
political dress within the Opposition. People who could not even
raise their faces to see us straight in our eyes because of their
shameful past are now draping themselves in the national flag as
vanguards in demonstrations and meetings. What a tragedy Ethiopians
have to endure? Even
some dare address and represent our voice in important meetings and
conferences. What is wrong with Ethiopians in the Diaspora these
days? There is not enough volume of perfume in the world that could
mask the stench of the Red Terror of Mengistu and his executioners
who caused the death and mutilation of hundreds of thousands of
Ethiopians. The Opposition must clean itself from such abominable
individuals before it can truly lead or be an important and
constructive political organization in Ethiopian politics. Ye woga biresa, yetewoga airesa!
Ethiopia was
profoundly affected by the involvement of foreign nations and
individuals for over a
century. There is a direct link between most of our current problems
with the events that took place in the past as a result of foreign
governmental interferences in the internal affairs of Ethiopia. Even
though we have now different actors with significant role in the
shaping of the current Ethiopian government policies and the cause
of the prevailing political disharmony, the characteristics of the
problem remains constant. History may be repeating itself in the
sense of the effort to destroy Ethiopia is very much underway with
new Governments at the helm of such effort. Ethiopians must be very
wary of the United States and Britain especially the United States
Government for its leaders lack consistency and long term strategic
planning ability or foresight.
Foreign
individuals who have played crucial roles in the modern history of
Ethiopia are few in number. Individuals such as Paul Henze are
household names in the Diaspora communities of Ethiopians around the
world. This is not an exaggeration but a matter of fact when one
examines what such individuals have done to deserve such ignominious
fame. For example, if we take into account Paul Henze�s recent
comment on the article by Christopher Clapham, we can observe that
the criticism goes far beyond critical analysis and is a polemical
advocacy defending the indefensible acts and policies of Meles
Zenawi and his government. At one point he even stooped so low to
state his personal relationship as the measurement for good
governance. Is this rationalism or an apology? May be it is neither
but the sad evidence of Henze�s disregard of the value of the
lives of Ethiopians. Is it possible for Henze to explain away the
gross disregard of the fundamental rights of Ethiopians, who were
massacred on November 1, 2005 and after, and the tens of thousands
arrested, dehumanized with atrocities to date? There is a danger of
becoming like the many Germen academics who were defenders of Hitler
and providers of his barbaric programs. Specially having read Max
Weinreech pioneering work on the role played by German academics, I
have the sickening feeling that Henze and others are doing the same
for Meles Zenawi and his regime.
Christopher
Clapham�s article is a rather mild criticism of the current
Ethiopian Government. Clapham is absolutely within his right to be
concerned about the ongoing Ethiopian political crisis for he is an
Ethiopian in a more meaningful way than most of us in the Diaspora.
He lived in Ethiopia, wrote his dissertation on Ethiopia, and had
had close contact with a number of Ethiopians and the nation itself
for decades. It is amazing to me why Henze jumped to attack Clapham,
when he should be encouraging healthy criticism of a leadership that
has turned its guns against its own people. I believe that Henze is
a very influential person within the United States Government, and
as a result has deformed America�s policy toward Ethiopia and its
leaders from 1975 to date. Because of such undue influence on the
government of the United States, Ethiopia to a significant extent is
driven into a political and economic quagmire. By simply following
his droppings of articles and essays for the last thirty years, one
can observe the terrible consequences of his activities in the
affairs of a sovereign nation. Henze�s hold on current Ethiopian
leaders has to do with the type of mystical and undefined role of
America�s leadership, the role of America�s security agency et
cetera.
2) Truth: Basic Understanding
When the
pre-Socratic philosophers [3] such as Thales, Aniximinder,
Pythagoras et cetera started asking fundamental questions as to the
nature of reality, such as what is the �stuff� everything is
made of or what is the common thing in all things, one may say
philosophy was born away into some thing more substantial than mere
myth and fables. However, such great start was brought to a
screeching stop by a question asked by another of the pre-Socratic
philosophers�Xenophanes. The question asked by Xenophanes was as
simple as it was thoroughly understandable. He simply asked how do
we know the truth when we get to it. Of course, not everything was
lost because of one philosopher�s superb question. Then came along
Parmenides, a few years younger than the rest, and probably the
greatest philosopher that ever lived, with answers on the
�unconcealment� of truth that to this day philosophers are in
some way using his ideas on the �unconcealment� or of
verification of truth.
In the fragments of the philosophical
writings of Parmenides, the philosopher tells us how he was received
by a �goddess� during his travels. Martin Heidegger in his
lecture titled �Parmenides and Heraclitus,� which was later
edited into a book [Parmenides],
devoted his analysis to that very identification of the
�Goddess� referred to by Parmenides. It is important that we
take note of the distinction that Parmenides is alleged to be making
by simply stating the identity of his hostess as the �Goddess�
Truth, i.e., Άλήθεια
(Aletheia), and not the �Goddess of Truth� if we accept the
interpretation by Heidegger. [4]
Truth may be one,
but how we get to know or approach that truth could be through
several ways coming from diverse directions as of necessity because
of the fact of multiple trajectory points as well as multiple
agents. Here is where one starts encountering problems for it is the
case that some philosophers as well as scientists overreach in
accepting their manner of inquiry or search methodology as the
finding of the �truth� that is the very center of disagreement
in contemporary philosophical and scientific enquiry.
Seen from such perspective truth seems to be multiple in some
aspect and �one� in another. Even with my limited understanding
Eastern philosophies, the Zen masters seem confused on questions of
truth and verification for they seem to be thorn between dualism and
monism in limited ontological understanding of being.
There are three
traditionally acknowledged theories dealing with the establishment
or verification of truth:
-
The Correspondence theory of truth[5]
-
The Coherence theory of truth [6]
-
The Pragmatic theory of truth [7]
However, I am
adding a fourth theory of truth, which is as capable in resolving
certain contested nature of reality as would be achieved by the
pragmatic theory of truth. Thus, the fourth I named as the
�agency� theory of Truth.
Each approach has
its strength and weakness that we can find out as we engage in our
quest for truth in establishing both metaphysical and physical
nature of reality. For example, the philosopher Popper surmised that
philosophical inquiry is not a search for truth, but an effort to
establish the falsehood of our assertions or beliefs. The world
perceived from such angle then becomes frightful to the individual
warping social life from being full of meaning and engagement. One
good reason for thinking about the nature of reality with a range of
possible levels of relationships is the fact that one is left open
to possibilities rather than with a conclusive and deterministic
universe.
Simply put, the
correspondence theory of truth or verification is the simplest and
most used by individuals from the existential to the metaphysical.
What the individual seeks is simply that his or her mental imagery
(?) corresponds to the physical reality that has an independence
from any individuality. Experienced nature without any mediation
except to record compare and contrast by our mind, if that is
possible at all, is what is meant by �correspondence� between
mind and the external. The problem of this approach is that there is
no real distinction in the theory that would allow us to
differentiate the quality of our observation as human beings with
the sight �observation� of other creatures. It adherers to the
idea that the human mind is like a photographic plate simply
recording reality. This type of �tabula-rasa� conception of the
mind and the nature of reality is not adequate on very many
important issues.
On the other hand
the coherence theory of truth and verification has far more
versatility than the more pedantic and straight-cut correspondence
theory of truth and verification, but may lack precision. The
coherence of other well-established theories or assumptions with the
new one introduced into the gauntlet is purely dependant not on
outside verification but rather on how well the new idea fits with
accepted theories. This approach is closer to the Parmenidean
approach of non-empirical knowledge formation and verification of
truth.
The great appeal
of the pragmatic conception of truth to some individuals seems to be
the fact of its emphasis on what is practical and of use to society
and the individual. It is one philosophical thinking that the United
States may claim some degree of origination or acknowledgement for
it is a home-grown philosophical thinking having its root in the
positivist thinking of Charles Pierce further developed by William
James. Dewey may be also credited for the humanist tradition in that
pragmatic rubric.
My own addition
to the understanding of what �truth� may be, which I have
identified as the �agency theory of truth� may be also
identified as the lazy-man�s truth. In this theory, the truth of a
claim is ascertained not by its ontology or
falsification/verification, but rather by looking at the credibility
of the person (agent) making such assertions. Under such
understanding of what �truth� is, it seems the hard work of
establishing the truth is already carried out by the individual
whose reputation as a scholar, moral teacher, et cetera has the
force of evidence or proof without any other reference.
Section III: Human Rights � The Case for
Universalism
The subject of human rights is best
understood in the life each of us live in a particular community.
Since definitions tend to freeze dynamic concepts, by my effort to
define or concreticize the concept of human rights, I may be
undermining what I am ultimately aiming at�the safeguard of
maximum human rights to all everywhere. A while back, I wrote in one
of my articles that life is not a set of multiple choices where one
can tick off right answers from a ready made and nicely fitting
clinical series. It is through living ones own life, warts and all,
that one may come close to answering fundamental inner and, at
times, universally felt questions. In that process, I believe, the
purpose of individual life is realized and maybe even fulfilled. The
issue of human rights seems to come into discussion in situations
where there is an expansion of an individual's interest affecting
and encroaching on the autonomy and integrity of other individuals.
In an ideal world where individuals have minimal contact with each
other and are able to act and do what they desire, there may not be
any dispute or controversy on questions of human rights. Thus, much
of the discussion of human rights is unduly affected by existential
factors such as acquisitive conflicts and power competitions, and
the general struggle for survival. On the other hand, without the
pressure of the struggle for survival and competition, we might have
stagnated as amoebas. With such understanding that life in general
is being shaped by forces beyond our control, I will attempt to
understand the role and scope of principles of human rights.
I believe that it is possible to discuss
human rights from three distinct approaches to justify or assert the
reality of human rights: the ontological approach; the religious
approach; and the evolutionary or biological approach.
a) The
ontological (epistemological) approach -
conceptualization of rights through purely intellectual
(analysis or synthesis) and intuitive processes, e.g. Plato's
republic, the categorical imperative of Kant, the 'will' generated
world-rights of Schopenhauer, rational liberal democracy of Rawls,
et cetera. As a subcategory, I have included the hermeneutical or
historical and structural approach, ideas mainly represented by
cultural and political relativism.
b)
The religious approach - the acceptance of Divine origin of man
thereby incorporating concepts that are contradictory of determinism
and inherent free will and rights in the soul of man. Most religious
dogmas dealing with the creation episode of man and the universe, as
represented by views of Hinduism on one side and Judio-Christian-Islam
theology on the other side, as well as ancient Pharaonic ideas of
creation and concepts of immortality, accountability; and
c) The evolutionary or biological approach
- empirical and corporeal development of ethics and morality as a
basis of human rights; Darwinian perception of the evolutionary
development of life and the corresponding evolutionary development
of cooperative effort of living beings as the source of ethics in
animals as expounded by Kropotkin, de Waal and others, as well as
the development of the human psyche as
expounded by Jung et cetera.
One other evidence of the universal nature
of human rights may be deduced from the way all human beings
recognize themselves and feel love, emotional pain (empathy), suffer
and mourn. The emotion of losing a beloved one, a friend, a child et
cetera, even if the expression of such feelings might differ, the
basic underlining emotion is universal. Similarly, the appreciation
of beauty, music or a good story is a human fact - all affirming the
universality of intimate emotions. Having said that, I believe there is more to rights beyond the 'human' ones.
Animals and all life in a way are also in the same continuum in the
larger sense of 'life' even if subjects of utilitarian perception of
them by human beings. It seems non-Western cultures are much more
aware of the deeper interconnection between all living things than
cultures in the West
.
The structuralist or relativist and
non-foundational perception of human rights is no less metaphysical
than the perception of the universalism of human rights. Even though
the claims of relativist non-foundational thinkers assert that
rights are social and cultural constructions or innovations that
facilitate better relationships between individuals and create
social cohesion, the fact of the mater is that such perception in
itself is also metaphysical if we use similar physicalist argument.
When I compare the three approaches
identified above, the weakest seems to be the religious approach and
the strongest seems to be the biological or empirical approach. One
cannot escape the unadulterated, maybe even crude, reality of
self-awareness, which might indicate that our very struggle for
existence could be seen as an affirmative evidence of the struggle
for autonomy (freedom) as well. Irrespective of whether we see the
'Divine' in man or in all of 'Creation' i.e., what has corporeal
existence, no one can doubt the enormity and complexity of the
question I am faced with in relation to the reality of my own
existence and by extension of things and being(s) outside of my
person. The very fact of the reality of 'being' as opposed to
'non-being' or 'nothing' is beyond human full comprehension
irrespective of the advantages or limitation of the dialectical
intimate relation between thinking and reality. Self-awareness
cannot be fully aware of itself. In this article what I am dealing
with is the relatively existential and limited issue of the concept
of human rights, and not about metaphysical concepts or theories of
knowledge and methodology. In these discussions of human rights
principles, there is an underlying assumption that my search is the
search for the truth and that truth when ever found is a good one.
Thus, perceived human rights is intimately connected with the search
for the truth, even though this may not be the classical search and
interpretation of truth in relation to nature, language, being, and
ethics.
1)
Ethics, Morality, and Truth:
I start this Section by asserting that the
awareness of having individual rights and the struggle to realize
such rights is as old as mankind and in some aspect even older
supra-species. It is extremely difficult to discuss the religious,
philosophical, sociological and jurisprudential issues involving
human rights in few pages. Other than the fact of presenting a
segmented picture of human rights, what I have done in this section
is to examine the history of human rights starting from a period a
few thousand years further into the remote past to a time where
mankind started out on an extraordinary journey in Africa and
crossed over into Asia and Europe and finally into the New World
(the Americas) down to our time. The awareness of having
�rights� might be the one true distinguishing feature of man
that sets him apart from other animals, especially from his fellow
primates.
The old ideas of demarcation of tool usage
and language as attributes of humankind only in order to accord
humankind a special place with rights and privileges are very much
obsolete concepts.[1] Moreover, any discussion of human rights based
solely on national and international law or custom and practices
without consideration of the process of evolution of societies
(groups) as well as the cognitive development of the individual
i.e., the psychological and sociological dimension of human
existence, is inadequate.[2] It seems that some scholars, who so
earnestly wrote on human rights issues, did not consider at all the
very basic 'humane' factor of the individual's moral and cognitive
development (psychological base) within a temporal and spatial
specificity (historical base). There are the exceptions who thought
of human rights as inherent, and moral development as inevitable
consequent in society.[3] Earlier scholars and their modern
counterparts who thought of human rights as inherent in human
beings, seem to have considered the psychological basis of human
rights in unbounded universe, a universe almost unanimous to the
concept of God. Their assertion of human rights as inherent in the
nature of man contrasts with views held by many contemporary
scholars[4] who seem to base their entire exposition of human rights
issues on the Modern Western superstructure of states (history) and
jurisprudential material of positivism and of critical theory.
The idea of human rights as transcendental
to history has very many attractive features; notwithstanding the
admonishment of the post-modernists (school of critical theory).[5]
If human rights is taken to be inherent, immutable or fundamental,
even where such assumption is wrong, it would still contribute to
positive human development. By comparison, if we accept the concept
of critical or contextual understanding of rights we would also have
to accept the appalling repressive social conditions (such as
slavery, Nazi concentration camps, colonization, cannibalism, human
sacrifice, caste systems, child labor, suppression of women, female
genital mutilation et cetera) in the past or in the present or in
the future as events neither bad or good,
without normative judgment or condemnation or possibility of
revolt. �Inherent� does not necessarily mean goodness; it simply
means that a quality is linked intimately and intrinsically with the
individual being.
I think critical theory is a methodology on
how to validate or weigh a positive assertion or proposition even
though the aim is not to ascertain truth or fallacy but to question.
Since it is a method of valuation of contradictions, it does not of
itself have independent and identifiable philosophical propositions
other than a philosophy on methodology. Unlike a philosophical
statement dealing with human rights, which does not need any other
condition for its consideration, critical theory necessarily, must
have a preexisting condition, such as a philosophical proposition,
in order to function or to have any meaning. The relationship
between critical theory and any other philosophical statement is
like the relationship between style and content or language and
thought or books/words and ideas therein�a method of measurement
can neither negate nor create elements of a thing (or a proposition
or a philosophy). At any rate, the fact of having a measurement or a
methodology does not of itself set limits to statements of
philosophy, or propositions et cetera. Reality maybe a lot more than
the description, impression, or expression of it. Recognition of
that does not in any way set limit to our thought process in our
effort to have a better grasp of reality. It simply is not enough to
tear down a social edifice no matter how useless without
understanding it expansively. The
value in a critical method of inquiry is in what it exposes as
weakness or strength (the contradictions) of an argument or a
statement, and more importantly in what it offers through its
implied negation, as an alternative choice or method of looking at a
hitherto accepted proposition or situation.
A far more epistemic (theory) statement
about critical theory "stresses that social research is itself
a form of social interaction in which the objects of knowledge are
potentially subjects of the very same knowledge, and thus it is
willy-nilly to a potential factor in changing social
relations."[6] In other words, critical theory is the
socio-political sieve that is supposed to catch pretenses and stupid
ideas, however that sieve needs to go through itself for the same
purpose. For example, by contrast to the progress of man�s
understanding of physical laws, say in the case of quantum physics
wherein a whole new language of higher mathematics was invented in
order to speak the language of the physical world more effectively,
in case of critical theorists no such comparable innovation in
language in order to deal with what is claimed to be a new
(different) philosophical departure. In other words, critical
theorists use more or less the language, logic, and
conceptualization of the old schools of philosophy.
I believe we could include the post-modern
philosophy of European anti-rationalism, namely deconstructionism,
as an aspect of critical theory.[7] In simple terms, the problem
with anti-rationalism philosophical theory is its super-fine tuning
and concentration on
non-content issues such as 'decentering' past philosophical
principles on the assumption that such philosophical works are
biased in favor of a dominant civilization. There is nothing wrong
with critical thinking and criticism. There is no doubt in my mind
about the fact that Derrida's approach and concern as quintessential
deconstructionist has merit, even maybe profound with deep
philosophical precepts. However, in the deconstruction process such
exercise is killing the patient as well while administering
allegedly curative potion. For example, in the case of decentering
(deconstructing) past Western philosophers, through my criticism of
deconstructionism, I attempting to bring to our attention the
relative importance of content over form. The fact that
deconstructionists tell us that Western philosophy is biased toward
the dominant Western culture, of itself does not remedy that
philosophical bias nor determine the issue of right and wrong. Even
more important is the acknowledgement that any demarcation is not
necessarily a limit to our ability. Thus, for example, the
issue of whether what is presented by an individual is better
presented in 'writing' or 'speaking' is of secondary importance.[8]
The problem of the significance of the form of presentation as
opposed to its content is not that new either. Starting from the
pre-Socratic philosophers such as Heraclitus [9] to date,
philosophers from varied schools of thought had struggled with the
problem of the contamination of content (subject) by the method of
delivery or communication of thought. [10] Thus, such insight on
epistemology maybe interesting but does not help much by way of
explanation or sourcing to our concern of human rights principles.
The obvious question that comes to mind is what is meant by human
rights. There is no conclusive record to show who used the term
�human rights� for the first time. However, the absence of
language designation does not imply the absence of awareness. People
can be so parochial that they will compete on anything to aggrandize
their own group or self. For example, as unbelievable as it is, one
author has asserted that the term was adopted for the first time in
the present century where its importance and applicability at
international level was reveled in 1948 by the United Nations'
Universal Declaration of Human Rights.[11] However, there are
several conclusive evidences the term �human rights� has been
used prior to 1948 or even prior to the Nineteenth Century. As a
matter of fact, in the 18th Century, an African slave (who later
bought his freedom from his White owner) wrote about how the
�human rights� of slaves was destroyed by slavers.
He wrote: "Our meeting affected all who saw us; and
indeed I must acknowledge, in honour of those sable destroyers of human
rights, that I never met with any ill treatment, or saw any
offered to their slaves, except trying them, when necessary, to keep
them from running away."[12] The term �human right�
was specifically used in the contest of its generally accepted
meaning by Olaudah Equiano (1735?-1797), an African slave, who later
was freed and lived in England as subject of the British Monarch.
There are numerous references to acts of oppression and appeals to
justice and human compassion in the Narratives as well as personal
letters to magazines and political personalities of the period.
What we have here is the impression of the teenage Olaudah (Vassa)
describing the behavior of his African slavers before he was sold to
a succession of owners. His usage of the term �human rights� is
precisely in the context of the modern concept of human rights that
we can relate to and understand in our own time.
2)
Civilizations and Universal Human Rights
It has been asserted by some scholars, such as Rhoda Howard, that
European civilization is the source of the foundational and
developmental ideas of human rights, and that the modern human
rights movement is based on Western tradition.[13] Other than
the facts of unwarranted assertions on African history and culture,
some of Howard's statements are blatantly racist or condescending,
to wit she stated: "A more charitable explanation may be that
African intellectuals are themselves victims of the intellectual
imperialism they so vigorously decry. Blocked in their earlier
attempts to Europeanize and join the dominant Western culture, they
instead adopted the long-standing Western myth of the noble savage
who exemplifies the virtues of generosity and self-sacrifice within
his own community. The noble savage is incapable of a selfish,
profit-seeking act. But he is also incapable of the scientific and
technological innovation that such selfishness allegedly impels, and
that is the basis of Western economic, political, and cultural
dominance in the contemporary world. The noble African is doomed to
stagnation in his closed, isolated, subsistence-level village, while
the mundane Westerner purses individual wealth and collective
economic prosperity in the modern city." (25)
This
type of claim of European (Western) source for human rights
principles is not limited to European or American writers. There are
also non-European who seem to have adopted such Eurocentric views
wholesale with minimal critical analysis of such assertions. [14] I
find this type of assertion to be a result of a narrowly constructed
meaning or understanding of the concept of human rights. Even worse,
it might be a racist and blatantly Eurocentric opinion. At ant rate,
the mere denotation or identification of fragments of human
experience does not mean the creation of those fragments. In other
words, unlike art, fragments of human experience do not acquire new
content by acts of mere recognition and by being placed in a
category.
This essay is not meant to undermine the contribution of Western
civilization to the advancement of humankind but to appreciate it in
the right context for its both destructive and constructive roles in
world civilization.[15] The term �Third World� was first
coined by the French demographer, Alfred Sauvy, who used tiers
monde the way the French have always used the term
tiers etat, i.e., the 'third estate' of
pre-revolutionary France. The first estate was the nobility, the
second the clergy and the third everybody else, including the
bourgeoisie, artisans, trades people and many others who were not
poor by a long sight. It is a good distinction to keep in mind these
days when 'Third World' tends to evoke undifferentiated misery. Not
everyone is poor there, as the book shows in some detail. "The
First World consists of developed market-economy countries
represented in the Organization for Economic Cooperation and
Development (OECD). The 'Second World' is some times used to refer
collectively to the socialist countries of the North - the USSR and
its satellites."] As
a matter of stark physical reality, and as observed by a
distinguished scholar, "[w]estern civilization has become what
might be called a 'super tradition' that remains resilient and
constantly influential because of the flexibility that reason gives
to its values, not because of a presumed superiority of any one of
the values it espouses."[16] However, it would be wise for the
rest of the world to weigh carefully the idea that a higher form of
civilization results also in higher moral development of the
individual in such civilized societies.
If we adopt the type of reasoning behind such claim of Eurocentric
perception of human rights, we ought to narrow further such
identification of human rights on questions of the development of
languages and semantics, for example. A critical
writing on Eurocentric traditions of analysis of history and
the over simplification of the history of Africa is thoughtfully
presented by Professor Clinton M. Jean.[17]
One such example is the attempted distinction between �human
rights� and �human dignity�.[18] "The argument
that different societies can have different concepts of rights is
based on an assumption that confuses human rights with human
dignity. All society have concepts of human dignity, but few accept
the notion of human rights, in the sense that individuals have the
right to make claims on or against the state."[19] The
difference between the two is that �rights� are conceptualized
as equally applicable to all human beings irrespective of their
individual circumstances, whereas �dignity� refers and depends
on individual circumstances. Although these types of
distinctions do not go to the core of real problems of
oppression, abuse et cetera, nevertheless, such distinctions have
created some confusion. Whether human dignity is a consequent or a
source of human rights, it is not an Earth shaking or a fundamental
distinction. To pursue this line of reasoning would give us
ridiculous results. This type of human rights understanding or
analysis is similar to one of earlier times ridiculous claim, by
over enthusiastic Western scholars, that the whole of philosophy was
a Western creation and that Africa did not make any contribution to
philosophy. This is one good example that illustrate the tyranny of
formalism over life experiences. Every human being has a philosophy
of life, that is how individuals see their connection with society
and nature. Without such a device of philosophical interface none of
the cultures or political structures in the world would have been
possible. It is as simple as that.
From history, we learn one important lesson the fact that violence has
been a permanent feature of civilizations; thus, may even be
inevitable. However, every generation need not repeat nor walk down
similar destructive routes of its forefathers. "Since time
immemorial man has longed for freedom and equality, for guaranteed
human rights and for fraternal relationships in a society in which
the people run and manage their own affairs." [20] Human rights
are not mere creation of international treaties, conventions or
municipal legislation (positive law) that came about after the
Second World War. [21] "Many discussion of the expansion
of human rights legislation and awareness seem to imply an
uninterrupted and easy development. This is misleading for at least
three reasons. First, it shows historical amnesia. The evolution of
human rights has been complex, convoluted, and bitterly resisted.
Though many people when they think of human rights think only of the
past few decades since World War II, the struggle to define and
protect human rights has lasted for centuries. Wars have been
fought, people tortured and murdered in the struggle for these
rights and laws. Each right represents prior bitter
experience...with what happened in the absence of that right's
legitimacy. Second, there are significant differences between the
idea (or, in this instance, the legal) and the real - that is,
between human rights as defined in law and treaty and as practiced
in the streets, barracks,
countryside, and frontier areas. All too often, governmental and
private prejudices, vested and conflicting interests, and simple
brutality intercede between law and practice. Universal standards of
moral behavior have been debated and agreed on in many state and
international laws, declarations, and conventions, but we are still
forced to witness every year the systematic and widespread abuse
around the world of these agreed-on human rights. The progressive
development of legal rights is beneficial because they provide
standards, goals, and a moral persuasion and pressure, but the
struggle must be fought on other fronts as well." [22]
Often
scholars have identified that concepts do not fit perfectly reality
or life on the ground. This should not come as a surprise to
anybody. Even as children we knew that ideas in our mind do not have
a one to one correspondence with things that we deal with in our
encounters with the reality around us. Contrary to the views of modern days legal positivists, the struggle
for human rights and the recognition of rights predates by thousands
of years our Twentieth Century treaties and conventions, and
municipal laws that deal with human rights. Even then, what treaties
and conventions, and municipal laws did was to acknowledge and
codify in a more formal setting a body of customary international
law on human rights. In other words, what treaties and conventions,
and municipal laws did was to codify what was already a subject of a
struggle and at times accepted to a significant depth. It is absurd
to think of human rights as a consequence of the experience of the
Second World War and the initiative of a handful of men, mostly
career diplomats and technocrats, and their counterparts in academia
from that time on. The struggle for freedom, for equal treatment,
for justice et cetera should not be considered detached from
mankind's struggle for existence.[23]
3)
Relativism: Self-Determination, Ethnic and Minority Rights
The after-birth of positivistic approach to
human rights is the structuralist approach to human rights. That
approach has elements of positivism and critical theory
methodologies. It is not a fully developed method, and at times
quite confusing. The fact that structuralism imputes the concept of
human rights with ideas that rights are divisible and interdependent
- the very reason used to support the structural approach -
undermines its validity.[24] Its proponents hail from both public
international professionals from organizations such as the United
Nations, World Bank et cetera, and from academia mostly individuals
who are connected with mildly activist human rights centers in some
American law schools. This structural approach "links human
rights to major world wide patterns and issues, identifies root
causes of violations, and recognizes the diversity of political and
social systems, cultural and religious pluralism, and different
levels of development."[25] All these may sound responsible,
democratic and concerned; however, the totality or the practical
effect would undoubtedly result in the creation of a hierarchy of
national groups and accord them different levels of human rights
with Third World peoples being at the bottom.
Thus, the structural approach to human
rights maybe seen as a thinly disguised racist idea of rights, or it
is a very elitist point of view, at best. One must realize that the
concept is self-serving, the group of people who would end up at the
top of the hierarchy will be White men and women of the
industrialized West irrespective of the devastating crimes committed
by the West on the rest of the world in the last one hundred years.
One must understand that development is not synonymous with good or
virtuous activities, or good morality or ethics, and even less with
good citizenship. The mere fact of being a Westerner should not be
taken as a demarcation for a separate set of human rights for
Westerners distinct from the rest of the world (mankind). There is
real danger of another horrendous genocide if we let the relativist
approach to human rights to culminate in its illogical conclusion.
The views of Michael Ignatieff in his Tanner Lecture at Princeton
(later published, Human Rights as Politics and as
Idolatry: The Tanner Lectures 1999)
outlined a conflicted interpretations of human rights principles�a
view that led him to support �pre-emptive strike� and the war on
Iraq. He expounded the view that human rights is not a matter of
fundamental or foundational principles, but rather an item that is
negotiated for and expedient. It is such structuralist understanding
of the concepts of human rights that inevitably led him to defend
the war on Iraq by the Bush/Cheney Government. The impact of his position was exponentially
magnified due to the fact that Ignatieff is an outstanding scholar
and the Director of the Human Rights Center at Harvard. (Some even
believe he might become the next Prime Minister of Canada.) To a
lesser extent Henry Steiner and Phillip Alston�s book, International
Human Rights in Context, which otherwise is an outstanding
textbook, also seems to be a relativist or structuralist book.[26]
These books seem to contextualize or existentialize human rights in
terms of socially constructed system of rights based on expediency,
at least that is what the titles of the books seem to suggest. In
addition, the title of the book by Steiner and Alston seems to
suggest a distinction between �international human rights� as
opposed to �national human rights� with a possible consequence
that human rights safeguard and practice in Western nations will be
distinctly different from the rest of the world. This suggests that
our international mess seems to be dealt with in a different and
watered down standard of human rights. If such is the true intention
of our contemporary scholars on human rights, it is indeed a
frightening prospect.
At the core of the thesis of the
structuralist or relativist human rights philosophers is a
misunderstanding of the concept of �universals� and
�universalism.� It seems they are building their understanding
of the concept of universalism as a type of inductive generalization
by simple enumeration. This is a mistake that has been repeated over
and over for thousands of years. The concept of �universalism�
need be discussed and understood through Parmenidean form of reason,
whereas relativistic propositions are existential items that can be
considered through observation and synthesis. In other words, this
type of limited understanding of �universal human rights� by
relativists is similar to the limited even faulty understanding of
the meaning of Platonic concept of the �Ideal� or the concept of
�Form� as understood by Aristotle. The motive of Ignatieff,
or Steiner and Alston, or very many scholars of human rights may not
be at all misanthropic, but a misunderstanding of the concept of
�universalism.� However, the effect of their work might
lead to such undesirable results. The reason I chose these
distinguished scholars discussed here above is because of the fact
of their impeccable record as human rights advocates and scholars of
great depth and understanding. I have also studied their work very
deeply. Thus, there can
be no other motive for the position these scholars took except for
their understanding of certain philosophical concepts erroneously.
One such misconception of the application
or operation of human rights principles is in the area delineated as
minority or ethnic rights. This is an improper use of the concept of
human rights in connection with minorities or ethnic groups. There
is no such thing as such that can be identified distinguishable as
�minority rights or �ethnic rights,� but rather we are dealing
with safeguards in the protection not to deny already universally
applicable rights to minorities and ethnic groups. It is not a case
of having a peculiar type of rights called �minority rights� or
�ethnic rights� as some additional �rights� of expanded or
original import. The international instruments applicable to the
issues of minority and/or ethnic rights are the same international
instruments. They are not different than the ones we refer to in
recognizing the civil and human rights of every individual in the
world.[27] Thus, when
there is a claim of minority or ethnic rights it is simply a claim
to have equal access to the universally declared or acknowledged
rights. As we can see from the many declarations, covenants,
conventions and resolutions, it is never meant or designed to
empower or endow minorities or ethnic groups with rights that are
different and superior to those recognized universally.
The confusion in this area of international
law principles and practices is due to the apparent contradiction of
the many declarations dealing with seemingly �unique rights� of
a protected group as entertained by several international
instruments, such as the Declaration on the Rights of Persons
Belonging to National or Ethnic, Religious or Linguistic Minorities
(1992); the Declaration on the Elimination of All Forms of
Intolerance and of Discrimination Based on Religion or Belief; the
declaration at the World Conference on Human Rights in Vienna
(1993); the declaration at the World Summit for Social Development
in Copenhagen; and the Habitate II conference in Istanbul and the
charter of the United Nations dealing with the issue of
self-determination.[28] The ILO convention of Indigenous
and Tribal Peoples Convention of 1957 and 1989 has simply added to
the confusion. It is important to reconcile these sets of principles
contained in such declarations specifically dealing with minorities
and ethnic groups with the universal declarations and covenants
dealing with universal principles of human rights.
In
support of the limited application of principles dealing with
self-determination issues, it is very enlightening to read the
recommendation of the watchdog institution within the United Nations
system itself namely the Office of the High Commissioner for Human
Rights. In 1996 the Office of the High Commissioner elaborated the
meaning and scope of self-determination as understood within the
United Nations system of several declarations, resolutions dealing
with the issue of �self-determination� and put a definitive
limit to the claims of every aspiring
�liberation� front to a rest. In Section 6 of its
Recommendation No. 21 it stated, �The Committee emphasizes that,
in accordance with the Declaration on Friendly Relations, none of
the Committee's actions shall be construed as authorizing or
encouraging any action which would dismember or impair, totally or
in part, the territorial integrity or political unity of sovereign
and independent States conducting themselves in compliance with
the principle of equal rights and self-determination of peoples and
possessing a Government representing the whole people belonging to
the territory, without distinction as to race, creed or colour. In
the view of the Committee, international law has not recognized a
general right of peoples unilaterally to declare secession from a
State.� (Emphasis mine)[29]
There
are also several interpretations by respected international law
experts supporting such interpretations of limiting the meaning and
import of the concept of self-determination. The
less contentious principles of protecting minorities and ethnic
groups and others is
not that difficult to understand in light of the above mentioned
recommendation on the far more challenging concept of
�self-determination� by the Office of the High Commissioner
as stated above. The obvious starting point under that regime
of international law principles is to identify minorities and ethnic
groups that are threatened with extinction, abuse, marginalization,
exclusion, et cetera if no step is taken to protect such endangered
groups. In the Ethiopian setting, there is none that could be seen
entitled to such protection. There is of course the question of
neglect in the sharing of resources, particular assistance, effort
to encourage social and political participation, but such
shortcoming on the part of the Ethiopian State does not amount to an
active persecution and immediate threat to the continued existence
of such groups.
The
many liberation movements that mushroomed in Ethiopia whether they
are Eritreans, Tygreans, Oromos, Somali, Sidama, Gambela et cetera
fall within the exigencies or constraints of that regime of
international law (cited herein above) that tells us none of such
movements could be considered legitimate in light of Ethiopian
socio-political reality. All such aggrieved groups need solve their
problems peacefully as part of the political and social process
within the state framework of Ethiopia. All liberation organizations
mentioned here in (except that of Eritrea that is in different
politically troublesome situation but no less illegal), as long as
their demand is for independence and secession as such, are illegal
and the Government of Ethiopia has the legal and moral right to
prosecute such divisionary or secessionist liberation movements. Any
government of a foreign state that gives sanctuary and military
assistance to such liberation movements is committing an illegal
act, and such involvement of a foreign state in the internal affair
of Ethiopia can be considered by Ethiopia as an act of hostility.
This includes the governments of several countries around the world
such as Egypt, Sudan, the many Arab states in the Middle East,
Britain, Canada, Italy, France, Germany, Pakistan, the United
States, governments involved in some form of illegal funding and/or
military assistance to such liberation movements.
Most
of the border conflicts whether it is in Africa, Asia, Latin
America, and even in present day Europe is a direct consequences of
the legacy left by the brutal colonialism of England, France, Italy,
Spain, Holland, and Germany. European
colonizers left in their former colonies troublesome legacies where
they continued to perpetuate their control and instigate conflict
between related groups of people who were either free or under
subjugation under contending European colonizers even though they
were all shared a common history before colonialism. A good example
is that of the new
state of �Eritrea� and
its parent country Ethiopia. Djibouti is another example
of a territory curved out of Ethiopia as a colonial beachhead
earlier and now as an independent nation serves as a French outpost
to keep an eye on the Red Sea passage (corridor) of vital business
and military strategic importance. Belize is another example of
England excess of slavery and serfdom, a pure creation of a British
plantation turned sovereign country at the cost of the parent
country of Guatemala. Kuwait is an example of a reneged enclave of a
minority group that is a bone inserted in the very throat of Iraq
siphoning off oil from a shared field of oil and depositing all that
wealth in British Banks. The United States, a new comer to the
drama, is acting out its ignoramus idea of self-determination on
Ethiopia favoring the secessionist Eritrean independent state and
undermining the very mother country of ancient linage.
Just
recently the United States Representative at the United Nations,
Ambassador Bolton, has admonished the Security Council to force
Ethiopia accept the Border Commission�s decision
of 2004, a decision that is entered in violation of international
human rights and the sovereignty of a Member State of the United
Nations. Moreover, the decision of the Border Commission was illegal
on procedural violations of impartiality and corruption of the
Commission Members. The Commission Chairman was working for the
United States as an attorney on record in a case before the ICJ [Avena
and Other Mexican Nationals (Mexico v. United States of America)]
and had long-standing relationship with the United States Government
at a time when he was also deciding the case on the border conflict
between �Eritrea� and Ethiopia. Virtually the Commission was a
one-man show of the Chairman since the other four Commission members
cancel out each other being appointed equally by the contending
parties. It is a fact that the United States was and still is an
interested party in the outcome of the border conflict between
Ethiopia and �Eritrea.� The decision of the Commission is a
corrupt one due to such conflict of interest of the Chairman of the
Commission and due to numerous other irregularities and lack of
capacity to arbitrate such a conflict. [30] Thus, for Ambassador
Bolton or any one else to insist that Ethiopia must accept such
illegal decision by the Border Commission is either a case of utter
ignorance of the principles and workings of international law and
processes or shameless arrogance of disregard of the rule of law.
All of the actions of the officials of the United States Government
is based on self-interest, in disregard of the legitimate rights of
millions of Afar Ethiopians affected by the boundary demarcation
in the disputed areas, and the historical rights of seventy
million Ethiopians in their territorial integrity of the Afar
Coastal territories and the territorial waters of the Red Sea.
In
a nutshell, such is the technical and close interpretation of the
regime of international law and principles applicable to problems of
minorities, ethnic groups and other protected persons and groups.
Are we heading anywhere with this type of analysis. Yes, we are. It
is important to understand that Ethiopia as a state is endowed with
tremendous power and privileges under international law. There is no
need to buckle every time some individual with questionable
following challenges the State of Ethiopia with some version of a
liberation movement. There
are sufficient legal actions that must be put into play with that
form of dissention. The right procedure is to take the matter
through a political and legal process. When it comes to our
relationship with the Government of the United States and European
national governments, the best approach is firmness and proper
legally defensible presentation of our interest.
4)
The Case of Ethiopia: Human Rights
The subject of human rights in the
Ethiopian setting is quite complex as is also the case in parts of
the world I have either visited or studied from news, books,
interviews et cetera. There seems to be similar pattern of abuse and
violations of the rights of the individual common in all societies,
the difference being in magnitude and spread. Ethiopia is a truly
ancient nation with a government and territory and a form of state
identity that literally dates back to the time of the Greek
civilizations. It is the one nation that had survived all these
thousands of years with an unbelievable degree of compactness and
territorial integrity and cultural hegemony.
In fact, it is an amazing history that is unique in its
longevity in all of the history of the lives of states or nations.
I just finished reading the multi-volume
seminal work of Arnold J. Toynbee, A Study of History, a work
I recommend to all who have time on their hands to read. Other than
the fact that the book is speculative in areas that Toynbee has no
expertise, I also realized how wrong the great historian was in his
book, in his own field of expertise (history), in dismissing
Ethiopia as a relic, a state stagnant in its own frozen culture
protected by its impenetrable natural barrier of dessert and high
escarpment. Despite the fact that Toynbee is an improvement on both
the 18th and 19th Centuries historians and
scholars representing the steepest decline of western scholarship
since the Middle Ages on the subject of the contribution of
non-western cultures and civilizations to the advancement of
mankind, I find his speculation that asserted only natural
phenomenon protected Ethiopians from colonization is simply rubbish.
What is also obvious in looking at the long history and
uninterrupted history of Ethiopia is the fact that the issue of
colonialism or colonial subjugation claim by anyone in the Ethiopian
setting simply shows misunderstanding of the process of the
evolution of states.
Human rights violations in Ethiopia
compared to other nations in the region or else where in the world,
to a great extent, is far less dehumanizing. The penal system in
Ethiopia is far more benign even under such poor human living
conditions. The humane content of punishment is far more pronounced
in any Ethiopian prison than prison systems I have read about else
where in the world. Ethiopians
are truly a great moral agents. If you seek in achieves and written
records, as well as oral tradition, except a couple of reports by
foreign travelers such as the sensationalist James Bruce, Ethiopians
hardly ever demonstrated the types of cruelty prevalent in Europe,
the Middle East, Asia et cetera. One may even consider our type of
punishment innocent and like a child�s play compared to the
innovative and utterly cruel forms of punishments practiced in other
communist around the world. We never have any form of stretching and
quartering of human beings while they are still alive as practiced
in England for centuries. We never had the �iron maid� that
medieval Europe developed to its macabre effect, we never developed
the impelling, crucifying, or of burning in huge bonfires of
individuals as a punishment. Even their Churches were not immune to
such barbarity when we think of the hundreds of thousands tortured
by their Inquisition and panels of learned churchmen. This is not to
deny past and current practices of Ethiopian Emperors and warlords
of administering some sever punishments like hanging, cutting off
limbs et cetera; however, the practice was very limited in scope and
not a fraction in its barbarity and violence compared to Europe and
their descendants that settled in Africa, the Americas, and Asia.
There is nothing Europe or Asia or America can teach us about
morality or virtuous behavior.
Let me ask a rhetorical question, what
nation having undergone the types of suffering that Ethiopians have
gone through would not have sold its soul? We have witnessed how
quickly individuals in the West faced with temporary set backs
revert to barbarism, and a good example is the looting, murder, et
cetera we all witnessed as reported by the media after the
destruction of some Southern States coastal areas by Hurricane
Katerina. Another example of much significance is the response of
President George Bush to the 9/11 attack and murder of innocent
people. Even if that violence was abhorrent, nevertheless the
response by the United States Government has violated a number of
internationally accepted principles on just wars. It is not morally
defensible when we consider the disproportional suffering unleashed
on innocent people where by his own admission Bush�s Government
has killed thirty thousand Iraqis most of whom innocent women and
children. At any rate, Iraq has nothing to do with the 9/11 attack.
Conservative estimate of the total number of innocent people killed
by American Government soldiers in Afghanistan and Iraq is over a
hundred thousand. What type of modern arithmetic would equalize the
lives of about three thousand Americans to be worth more than a
hundred thousand Iraqis and Afghans? Are Western politicians the
types of moral human beings in any position to preach to us about
ethical behavior and human rights?
Human rights concept in its subdivision or entirety is our
making and not that of the West. It is ironic that the children of
colonialists and genocide perpetrators claiming the higher ground of
morality when we know that all of our problems around the world are
traceable to their aggressive and violent legacy.
Do I have to be grateful for not being
molested by this government or that government for my out spoken
words? Not at all, I have every right to be here or else where in
the world, and I have the unalienable freedom to speak my mind.
Gratitude for not being violated is not a virtue, but a morality of
a caged soul. To use force against me for my exercise of my natural
and fundamental rights and for making an ethical stand is simply a
demonstration of the moral degeneration of the party who dare attack
me for my being or my presence or my conscious. Ultimately, the
truth is the final arbiter of our humanity�and that truth so far
points at the singular barbarism of Western governments throughout
history.
In conclusion, I emphasize the fact that we
Ethiopians never built a Coliseum in order to watch human beings
killing each other or being mauled and killed by wild animals. We
did not build concentration camps where millions were starved,
gassed, brutalized to death. We did not burn hundreds of thousands
of people for religious reason. We did not create gulags
and slave camps where millions were worked to their bones and to
their death. We did not commit genocide of millions of people so
that our own people could claim the land of the exterminated
indigenous population. It is absurd even to think that such people
with such blood-socked history are also the agents who established,
safeguarded, and defended human rights. Instead, we are the
originators and champions of human rights! END OF SERIES
Tecola W. Hagos
December 15, 2005
Copyright
� by Phineaus St. Claire, Washington DC. December 15 2005.
Footnote
limited to few indicative sources:
Section
I.
- See G. Woodcock, Toronto:
Canadian Broadcasting Corporation, (1966); and Ronald Bleiker, Popular
Dissent, Human Agency, and Global Politics, Cambridge UK:
Cambridge University Press (2000).
- Plato, Crito,
Trans. Benjamin Jowett, The Harvard Classics,
Ed. Charles W. Elliot, New York NY: P. F. Collier &
Sons, 1937.
- John Rawls, Theory
of Justice; Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press,
1971; - �Civil Disobedience and the Social Contract,� in
Law and
Philosophy, ed. Sidny Hook, New York: New York
University Press, 1968.
- Henery Daivid Thoreau, Civil Disobedience, (1849).
- Leo Tolstoy,
Tolstoy's Writings on Civil Disobedience and Non-violence.
New York NY: Bergman Publishers, 1967.
- Mahatma Gandhi, Non-Violent
Resistance (Satyagraha),
(originally
published by the Navjivan Trust, Ahmedabad India 1951)
Mineola, NY: Dover Publications, 2001; - Satyagraha
in South Africa. Ahmedabad, India: Navajivan Publishing
House, 1950.
- Martin Luther King, Why We
Can�t Wait, New York NY: Harper & Row, 1964.
- John Rawls, �Civil
Disobedience and the Social Contract� in Law
and Philosophy, ed. Sidney Hook, New York NY: New York
University Press, 1968; Further elaborated version included as
Part Two in A Theory of Justice, Cambridge MA: Harvard
University Press, 1971.
- John Rawls, Ibid
- Getatchew Haile, �Criticism without Substance,� Ethiomedia,
November 17, 2005.
- Getatchew Haile, Ibid
- Minasse Haile, �Comparing human rights in two Ethiopian
constitutions: the Emperor's and the �Republic's��--cucullus
non facit monachum. 13 Cardozo J. Int'l & Comp. L. 1-59
(2005); - "The New Ethiopian Constitution: Its Impact Upon
Unity, Human Rights, and Development," 20
SUFFOLK TRANSNAT'l l. REV. 1 (1996).
- Getatchew Haile, �Criticism without Substance,�
(November 17 �05, Ethiomedia.
Section II
- L.
Jonathan Cohen, The
Dialogue of Reason: An Analysis of Analytical Philosophy,
Oxford UK: Oxford University Press, 1986; L.O. Urmson, Philosophical
Analysis: Its Development Between the Two World Wars,
Oxford UK: Oxford University Press, 1956;
R. Carnap, Meaning
and Necessity, Chicago IL: Chicago University Press,
1956. Jacques Derrida, Of Grammatology,
translated by Gayatri Chakravorty Spivak, Baltimore MD: The
Johns Hopkins University Press, 1974.
- Flipe Fernandez-Armesto, Truth:
A Guide for the Perplexed (Black Swan, 1998).
- John
Burnet, Early Greek Philosophy, (1930) London UK: Macmillan; -
Kathleen Freeman, Ancilla
to Pre-Socratic Philosophers, Cambridge MA: Harvard
University Press 2003; - G.S. Kirk, J.E. Raven, and M.
Schofield, The Presocratic Philosophers: A Critical History with a
Selection of Texts, 2nd
ed., Cambridge UK: Cambridge University Press, 1995.
- Martine
Heidegger, Parmenides, Trans. Andre Schuwer and Richard Rojcewicz,
Bloomington IN: Indiana University Press, 1998.
- O'Connor,
D. J., The Correspondence Theory of Truth,
London: Hutchinson, 1975.
- Frederick F. Schmitt, ed. Theories of Truth,
Oxford: Blackwell, 2003; Nicholas Rescher,
1973, The Coherence Theory of Truth,
Oxford UK: Oxford University Press, 1982.
- William James. Pragmatism: A New Name for Some Old Ways of Thinking.
New York: Longman Green and Co., 1907
Section III:
- There are many
publications, both scientific and popular, on the topic about
comparative valuation of human and animal behavior. The one book
I found to be extremely enlightening as well as very disturbing
is the book by Dale Peterson and Jane Goodall, Visions
of Caliban: On Chimpanzees and People, Boston and New
York: Houghton Mifflin Company, 1993.
- There are numerous books
on the moral and cognitive developments of human beings. At the
very least, any person writing on issues of human rights must
read the following books: Robert Coles, The
Moral Life of Children, Boston: Houghton Mifflin
Company, 1987; Lawrence
Kohlberg, Philosophy of
Moral Development, New York: Harper & Row, 1981;
Gareth Matthew, Philosophy
and the Young Child, Cambridge MA: Harvard University
Press, 1980; and Jean
Piaget, Moral Judgment of the Child, New York: Free Press, 1965.
Even if we do not get total illumination on moral development by
reading these books, at least we will be able to gain some
insight as to the development of values of people who are not of
our 'civilization' that would make us a lot less disparaging and
judgmental about their humanity and sense of worth.
- Frans de Waal, Good
Natured: The Origins of Right and Wrong in Humans and Other
Animals, Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press, 1996; -
Murray Bookchin, The
Ecology of Freedom: the Emergence and Dissolution of Hierarchy,
Montreal & New York: Black Rose Books, 1991.
- Jack Donnelly, Universal
Human Rights in Theory and Practice, Ithaca, NY: Cornell
University Press, 1989. "Human rights represent a
distinctive set of social practices, tied to particular notions
of human dignity, that initially arose in the modern West in
response to the social and political changes produced by modern
states and modern capitalist market economies. Most non-Western
cultural and political tradition, like the premodern West,
lacked not only the practice of human rights but also the very
concept." (50)]
- David Couzens Hoy and
Thomas McCarthy, Critical
Theory, Oxford UK and Cambridge M: Blackwell Publishers,
1994. "Exclusively deconstructionist approaches fail to
appreciate that the unconditionality of ideas of reason harbors
not only a dogmatic but a subversive potential:
context-transcendent claims to validity are permanently exposed
to criticism from all sides. Postmodernist critique is itself
unintelligible without this, that is, without the supposition
that the received views it criticizes claim a validity
transcending the contexts in which they were put forward.
Understood pragmatically, then, the unconditionality of validity
claims also runs counter to what its postmodernist critics
suppose - toward the ongoing critique of dogmatism, error, and
self-deception in all other forms." (37)
- Goran Hyden, "The
Challenges of Domesticating Rights in Africa," in Human
Rights and Governance in Africa, Roland Cohen, Goran
Hyden, and Winston P.Nagan eds., Gainsville FL: University Press
of Florida, 1993, 16.
- See Jacques Derrida, Of Grammatology, trans. Gayatri Spivak, John Hopkins
University press, 1976; - Specters
of Marx: The State of the Debt, the Work of Mourning, and the
New International, trans. Peggy Kamuf, New York and
London: Routledge, 1994.
- Jacques Derrida, Positions,
trans. Alan Bass, Chicago: Chicago University Press, 1981, 22; Margins
of Philosophy, trans. and additional notes Alan Bass,
Chicago: Chicago University Press, 1982, talking 88-108, writing
309-330;
- G.S.Kirk, J.E.Raven and
M.Schofield, (1957) The
Presocratic Philosophers: A Critical History With a Selection of
Texts, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2nd ed.,
1995, 181-212.
- David Roochnik, The
Tragedy of Reason: Toward a Platonic Conception of Logos,
New York and London: Routledge, Chapman and hall Inc., 1990,
132-139.
- Attar Chand, Politics
of Human Rights and Civil Liberties: A Global Survey,
Delhi: K.K. Thukral, UDH Publishers, 1985, 44-45. - The
Universal Declaration of Human Rights, United Nations General
Assembly Resolution 217A(III), UN Doc. A/810 (1948). see
Appendix I; Johannes Morsink, The Universal Declaration of Human Rights: Origins, Drafting and
Intent, Philadelphia
PA: University of Pennsylvania Press, 1999
- Olaudah Equiano, (1795) The Interesting Narrative and Other Writings, ed.
Vincent Carretta New York: Penguin Classics, 1995, 51. (emphasis
added)
- See Jack Donnelly, Universal Human Rights in Theory and Practice, Ithaca
NY: Cornell University Press, 1989; Rhoda E. Howard, Human
Rights in Commonwealth Africa, Totowa NJ: Rowman &
Littlefield, 1986.
- See Bassam Tibi, "The
European Tradition of Human Rights and the Culture of
Islam" in Human Rights in Africa: Cross-Cultural Perspectives,
104-132, Abdullahi
A. An-Na'im and Francis M. Deng ed., Washington D.C: The
Brookings Institution, 1990.
- Jon Bennett with Susan
George, The hunger Machine: The Politics of Food, Cambridge GB:
CBC Enterprise, 1987, 5-6.
- Goran Hyden, "The
Challenges of Domesticating Rights in Africa," in Human
Rights and Governance in Africa, 257, Roland Cohen,
Goran Hyden, and Winston P.Nagan eds., Gainsville FL: University
Press of Florida, 1993.
- See Clinton M. Jean, Behind The Eurocentric Veils: The Search for African Realities,
Amherst MA: The University of Massachusetts Press, 1991.
- Rhoda E. Howard, Human
Rights in Commonwealth Africa, Totowa NJ: Rowman &
Littlefield, 1986.17-23
- See also Timothy
Fernyhough, "Human Rights and Precolonial Africa," Human
Rights and Governance in Africa, supra note 16, at
41-53. - The Constitution of the Federal Democratic Republic of
Ethiopia [hereinafter the Constitution], Article 10 (1) �Human
rights and freedoms inviolable and inalienable. They are
inherent in the dignity of human beings.� (2) �Human and
democratic rights of Ethiopian citizens shall be respected.�
- Attar Chand, Politics
of Human Rights and Civil Liberties: A Global Survey, Delhi,
India: KK Thukral, UDH Publishers, 1985, 16.
- Art Hansen, "African
Refugees: Defining And Defending Their Human Rights," Human
Rights and Governance in Africa, Supra note 16, at
139-167.
- See
Attat Chand, Politics
of Human Rights and Civil Liberties: A Global Survey,
supra note 20, 15-16.
- Henry Steiner and Phillip
Alston, International
Human Rights in Context: Law, Politics, Morals, Oxford:
Oxford University Press, 1996; - A.J.M. Milane, Human
Rights and Human Diversity: An Essay in the Philosophy of Human
Rights, London: Macmillan, 1986;
- John Finnis, Natural
Law and Natural Rights, Oxford: Oxford University Press,
1980; - Leo Strauss, (1950) Natural
Right and History, Chicago and London: The University of
Chicago Press, 1965.
- See Henry Shue, Basic
Rights: Subsistence, Affluence, and U.S. Foreign Policy,
Princeton NJ: Princeton University Press, 1980.
- Claude E.Welch, Protecting
Human Rights in Africa, Philadelphia: University of
Pennsylvania Press, 1995, 276.
- Michael Ignatieff, The
Lesser Evil: Political Ethics in an Age of Terror. Princeton
University Press, 2004; - Empire
Lite: Nation-Building in Bosnia, Kosovo and Afghanistan.
Penguin, 2003; - Human Rights as Politics and Idolatry.
Princeton University Press, 2003; - Human
Rights as Politics and as Idolatry: The Tanner Lectures 1999.
Princeton University Press, 2001; Henry
Steiner and Phillip Alston, International
Human Rights in Context: Law, Politics, Morals, Oxford:
Oxford University Press, 1996
- -
Universal Declaration of Human Rights (1948) (UDHR) (article 2,
7); - Convention Relating to the Status of Refugees (1951)
(article 1, 3);
- Declaration on the Granting of Independence to Colonial
Countries and Peoples, GA
Resolution (1960)
-
United Nations Declaration on the Elimination of all Forms of Racial
Discrimination
(1963)
-
International Convention on the
Elimination of All Forms of Racial Discrimination (1965) This treaty
entered into force in 1969. This is the most comprehensive treaty
concerning the rights of racial and ethnic minorities. It lays down
in detail the steps required by states to prevent racial
discrimination and violence and to foster greater racial harmony;
-
International Convention on
Economic, Social and Culture Rights (1966) (article 2 );
-
International Covenant on Civil and
Political Rights (1966) (article 2, 20, 26, 27)
The Covenant lays out the principle that Rights are to all
"without distinction of any kind, such as race, colour, sex,
language, religion, political or other opinion, national or social
origin, property, birth or other status" (article 2).
Governments are charged with the responsibilities to prohibit by law
any "national, racial or religious hatred that constitutes
incitement to discrimination, hostility or violence" (article
20). The Covenant provides also the equal treatment before the law
without any discrimination to the equal protection of the law
(article 26). �Minorities shall not be denied the right, in
community with the other members of their group, to enjoy their own
culture, to profess and practice their own religion, or to use their
own language� (article 27);
-
Convention on the Elimination of All Forms of Discrimination Against
Women (1979);
-
Rome Statute of the International Criminal Court (1998) [articles 6
and 7(j)]
The statute of the International Criminal Court (ICC) gives the
court jurisdiction over acts of genocide of specific national,
ethnic, racial or religious groups under article 6. Apartheid
is further defined as a crime against humanity in article 7(j).
- The
Declaration on the Rights of Persons Belonging to National or
Ethnic,
Religious
or Linguistic Minorities (1992); the Declaration on the
Elimination of All Forms of Intolerance and of Discrimination
Based on Religion or Belief; the declaration at the World
Conference on Human Rights in Vienna (1993); the declaration at
the World Summit for Social Development in Coppenhagen; and the
Habitate II conference in Istanbul and the charter of the United
Nations dealing with the issue of self-determination. The ILO
convention of Indigenous
and Tribal Peoples Convention of 1957 and 1989.
- Office
of High Commissioner For Human Rights - General Recommendation
No. 21: Right to
Self-Determination: -23/08/96 (Fortyeighth Session,1996)
1. The Committee notes that ethnic or religious groups or
minorities frequently refer to the right to self-determination
as a basis for an alleged right to secession. In this connection
the Committee wishes to express the following views.
2. The right to self-determination of peoples is a fundamental
principle of international law. It is enshrined in article 1 of
the Charter of the United Nations, in article 1 of the
International Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights
and article 1 of the International Covenant on Civil and
Political Rights, as well as in other international human rights
instruments. The International Covenant on Civil and Political
Rights provides for the rights of peoples to self-determination
besides the right of ethnic, religious or linguistic minorities
to enjoy their own culture, to profess and practice their own
religion or to use their own language.
3. The Committee emphasizes that in accordance with the
Declaration on Principles of International Law concerning
Friendly Relations and Cooperation among States in accordance
with the Charter of the United Nations, approved by the United
Nations General Assembly in its resolution 2625 (XXV) of 24
October 1970, it is the duty of States to promote the right to
self-determination of peoples. But the implementation of the
principle of self-determination requires every State to promote,
through joint and separate action, universal respect for and
observance of human rights and fundamental freedoms in
accordance with the Charter of the United Nations. In this
context the Committee draws the attention of Governments to the
Declaration on the Rights of Persons Belonging to National or
Ethnic, Religious and Linguistic Minorities, adopted by the
General Assembly in its resolution 47/135 of 18 December 1992.
4. In respect of the self-determination of peoples two aspects
have to be distinguished. The right to self-determination of
peoples has an internal aspect, that is to say, the rights of
all peoples to pursue freely their economic, social and cultural
development without outside interference. In that respect there
exists a link with the right of every citizen to take part in
the conduct of public affairs at any level, as referred to in
article 5 (c) of the International Convention on the Elimination
of All Forms of Racial Discrimination. In consequence,
Governments are to represent the whole population without
distinction as to race, colour, descent or national or ethnic
origin. The external aspect of self-determination implies that
all peoples have the right to determine freely their political
status and their place in the international community based upon
the principle of equal rights and exemplified by the liberation
of peoples from colonialism and by the prohibition to subject
peoples to alien subjugation, domination and exploitation.
5. In order to respect fully the rights of all peoples within a
State, Governments are again called upon to adhere to and
implement fully the international human rights instruments and
in particular the International Convention on the Elimination of
All Forms of Racial Discrimination. Concern for the protection
of individual rights without discrimination on racial, ethnic,
tribal, religious or other grounds must guide the policies of
Governments. In accordance with article 2 of the International
Convention on the Elimination of All Forms of Racial
Discrimination and other relevant international documents,
Governments should be sensitive towards the rights of persons
belonging to ethnic groups, particularly their right to lead
lives of dignity, to preserve their culture, to share equitably
in the fruits of national growth and to play their part in the
Government of the country of which they are citizens. Also,
Governments should consider, within their respective
constitutional frameworks, vesting persons belonging to ethnic
or linguistic groups comprised of their citizens, where
appropriate, with the right to engage in activities which are
particularly relevant to the preservation of the identity of
such persons or groups.
6.The
Committee emphasizes that, in accordance with the Declaration on
Friendly Relations, none of the Committee's actions shall be
construed as authorizing or encouraging any action which would
dismember or impair, totally or in part, the territorial integrity
or political unity of sovereign and independent States conducting
themselves in compliance with the principle of equal rights and
self-determination of peoples and possessing a Government
representing the whole people belonging to the territory, without
distinction as to race, creed or colour. In the view of the
Committee, international law has not recognized a general right of
peoples unilaterally to declare secession from a State. In this
respect, the
7.Committee
follows the views expressed in An Agenda for Peace (paras. 17 and
following), namely, that a fragmentation of States may be
detrimental to the protection of human rights, as well as to the
preservation of peace and security. This does not, however, exclude
the possibility of arrangements reached by free agreements of all
parties concerned.
30.
Hereunder I have excerpted a very important item from an
article I wrote and posted in this Website on October 23, 2003 on
the illegality of the Border Commission and the invalidity of its
decision.
�..
2.
Conflict of Interest: Disqualification of Lauterpacht: All
international adjudication/arbitration forums have certain standards
of integrity that must be upheld by members of such
forums/courts/tribunals/commissions. The basic documents of the ICJ
as well as that of the International Permanent Court of Arbitration
and the UNCITRAL rules all have provisions providing for �high
moral� standards that members sitting to adjudicate or advise or
arbitrate parties to a controversy and the world at large are
expected and required to observe. The independence of any such body
from undue influence of third parties is a well established
principle that evolved out of centuries of the development of
customary international law and principles. We have to consider also
general principles of law practiced by all �civilized nations�
of the World in connection with the integrity of an international
court or forum Article 2 of the Statue of the ICJ holds that
�[t]he Court shall be composed of a body of independent
judges, elected... from among persons of high moral
character.� [Emphasis added]
Article
23 of the 1899 basic document that created the Permanent Court of
Arbitration [Convention for the Pacific Settlement of International
Dispute] holds that �each Signatory Power shall select four
persons...of known competency in questions of international law, of the
highest moral reputation, and disposed to accept the duties of
Arbitrators.� [Emphasis added]
From
the verse quoted here from the Bible, at least, we should consider
its moral teaching.
�For
where your treasure is, there will your heart be also.� Matt. 6:21
We
should understand the role of arbitrators to be distinct from that
of ICJ judges in context of how arbitrators are chosen or appointed
in the first place. However, this does not mean that we have to
throw out all professional ethical standards when it comes to
arbitrators. By the nature of their appointment or election,
arbitrators do have certain preferences in supporting the position
of the party that appointed or elected them. However, this does not
mean that they are not bound by the �highest moral reputation�
standard. It may be argued that that their preference to the party
that appointed them may not disqualify them from being arbitrators.
However, when it comes to the president or chairman elected by the
arbitrators themselves pursuant to the arbitration agreed upon
procedure, I believe both standards of �independence� and
�highest moral reputation� standards are applicable to
arbitrators who are thus elected by the other arbitrators to be
presidents of particular commissions or tribunals.
The
Commission members, especially the President, Sir Elihu Lauterpacht,
have displayed an unusually blatant disregard of both the �high
moral� standard expected of his position and impropriety in his
activities that clearly shows his lack of independence from the
influence of third party governments. It is with sincere regret that
one is forced to challenge Lauterpacht�s professional ethical
standard due to the gravity of the problem facing one�s nation.
Lauterpacht is a seventy five year old international jurist who had
led a distinguished life until this moment.
Lauterpacht
has displayed a degree of liberties in his words of communication
with the Government of Ethiopia that boarders an impertinence. He
seems to have cast his role as an ICJ judge or a �Secretary
General� of an international organization like the United Nations
rather than a �President� of a privately established arbitration
tribunal. Let us consider the situation in a holistic manner taking
into account other activities of undue interferences by third
parties that may have direct bearing on the Ethiopia-Eritrea border
dispute. Not withstanding the hollow diatribe of the Representative
of �Eritrea� at the recent General Assembly of the United
Nations, looked at with such global perspective, the
Ethiopia-Eritrea Border Commission arbitration process is in a real
mess. The Security Council, and the Secretary General are assuming
roles that was never envisioned or authorized through
practice�roles of a Judiciary (a supreme court) and that of a
Chief �Justice.
Thus,
it is obvious that the United States is acting in an adversarial
role in the case involving the border dispute between Ethiopia and
Eritrea. It is no more an impartial neutral body. With such public
background in full view, the United States has further stained the
arbitration process with its uncouth act of retaining as its lawyer
Lauterpacht in its case with Mexico, a case pending at the ICJ [Avena
and Other Mexican Nationals (Mexico v. United States of America)].
This act of the United States is no different, for example, from
Eritrea hiring Lauterpacht to work on some legal case while
Lauterpacht is still a member of the Commission. If that was the
case, everybody with some legal background would have called out
�conflict of interest� at the top of his or her voice. Thus, the
fact of an interested party such as the United States retaining a
sitting-Commissioner as its lawyer is only slightly a shade
different than the actual party in the controversy�Ethiopia or
�Eritrea��retaining any of the sitting-Commissioners as a
private lawyer. It does not in any way mitigate the unethical and
conflict of interest situation by identifying when Lauterpacht was
retained as counsel for the United States, rather what remains is
the negative shadow cast on the fitness of Lauterpacht as an
arbitrator and the independence of the Commission as a whole. One
must realize the Commission�s work is not yet concluded, thus the
members of the Commission are still bound by the standards set by
the Basic document of the Court of Arbitration and principles
developed for such purposes by customary international law.
It
is only proper for Ethiopia to demand full disclosure by Lauterpacht
of all his activities with third parties that are directly or
remotely involved with the on going border dispute with Eritrea. If
this is not a clear case of conflict of interest, loss of
independence, and a compromise of the principle of �high moral�
standing expected and required of the members of the Commission,
show me what is.
Not
only Lauterpacht is personally involved in such blatant conflict of
interest, but also Riesman, another member of the Commission
appointed by Eritrea, is involved in other cases that put his
behavior in a compromised position. It seems that Lauterpacht is
using the Permanent Court of Arbitration based commissions and
tribunals as his private law firm away from his home base from his
Chambers at 20 Essex Street. His partner Arthur Watts at the
Chambers at 20 Essex Street is supposedly picked by Ethiopia for the
Commission. Here you have an incestuous relationship where the same
characters are showing up again and again as commission or tribunal
members. Both the appearance of conflict of interest or conflict of
interest in fact is rampant in the whole arbitration process where
the �high moral� and �independence� standards are
compromised.
Ideally,
international arbitration was to be carried out by choosing from the
members of the Permanent Court of Arbitration already designated by
their respective governments who are signatories of the 1899 or 1907
Treaties (Conventions). With the adoption of the UNCITRAL rules the
forum was expanded to include ad hoc arbitrators who are not
designated by any member nations. This process seems to have opened
the door for corruption and conflict of interest problems. One must
not lose sight of the initial reasons why in 1899 the arbitration
forum was needed. It seems there was an interest by the kings,
queens, heads of States et cetera who meet at the Hague an idealized
element of public duty to bring about peace and security to a Europe
and a world at large racked with war and violence and �to record
in an international agreement the principles of equity and right on
which are based the security of States and the welfare of
peoples,� [Preamble, 1899 Convention]. It was envisioned that
seasoned statesmen and international law jurists would help
stabilize the world through their wisdom by arbitrating conflicting
claims by states. It was never meant a career promoting and money
making scheme for lawyers.
Looking
at the record of the last three to four years, one cannot but notice
that Lauterpacht and a few of his exclusive group of individuals
seem to have made the process of �arbitration� a money making
mechanism for their insatiable appetite for money. Most anyone would
be tempted with the prospect of earning an exorbitant amount of
money at an hourly rate of 200 to 300 hundred dollars. When I
examined the docket of the Permanent Court of Arbitration ad hoc
tribunals and commissions, I was amazed to read how Lauterpacht and
Riesman seem to have their hands in every pot. Are these individuals
truly �disposed to accept the duties of Arbitrators� or are they
involved in some kind of money making scheme that compromised and
defeated the purpose of having an arbitration in the first place?
Raising
the issue of professional responsibility (conflict of interest,
corruption et cetera) is a very sensitive and complex matter for
anyone. It should not be a point of contention without solid ground.
I have first hand experience of good intentions going sour and
affecting the judicial system. The psychology of the individual
involved is not that important in determining such issues. After all
the history of mankind�s failure is littered with good intentions.
Neither accusing the messenger of personal misdeeds nor giving
examples of the trespasses of others can mitigate the harm done as a
result of practices by a couple of Commissioners that undermined the
integrity of the arbitration process and the rule of law in general.
It is with great concern that I have addressed the issues discussed
in this article.
The
Government of Ethiopia has every right to void all agreements,
including the Algiers Agreement, and to reject the entire decision
of the Commission. Ethiopia cannot be obliged to accept a decision
by a Commission that is corrupted where some members of the
Commission have compromised their duty to exercise
�independence� and �high moral� standards. It is not
important to show that all and every member of the Commission is
involved in such conflict of interest. As long as one can show at
least one member is involved in such conflict of interest, the
entire proceeding and all decisions thereof, which flowed from such
process, are tainted, thus void. Ethiopia should demand the
disqualification of the President of the Commission, Elihu
Lauterpacht, for conflict of interest and corruption.
_____________________________________
Copyright � by
Phineaus St. Claire, Washington DC. December 15 2005.
|