In Defense of Pope Benedict XVI: A Case for Freedom of Thought
and Expression
By Tecola Hagos (September
16, 2006)
The
recent uproar by a number of politicians and religious leaders in a number
of Moslem countries, ironically including the Patriarch of the Coptic
Church in Egypt, may be a simple manifestation of underlying frustration
of the hundreds of millions of Moslems in the ongoing unresolved conflicts
between Israel and Palestinians, and the United States and several
millions Arabs in many of the Arab nations such as Lebanon, Iraq, Saudi
Arabia, Jordan et cetera. In any fair reading of the text of the speech
given by Pope Benedict XVI at the University of Regensburg,
Germany, on 12 September 2006 is not anti-Moslems nor insulting of the Prophet.
The speech is a typical speech by an academic raising points of particular
interest for discussion and understanding. The speech by the Pope is
rather well written and thoroughly apolitical, and surprisingly so in time
where you find so much garbage being thrown in our faces from politicians
and religious leaders all over the world. The speech is full of eloquently
expressed views of an original man of letters and of great learning. I
find it very difficult to imagine that any reasonable person can find any
politically based barb or hidden or overt anti-Moslem sentiment or
statement in that speech. What a number of people have pointed out to be
as the offending material in the Pontiff�s speech is in fact quoted
lines from statements made in the 14th Century by an Emperor of
Byzantium, which was being challenged by the Pope rather than endorsed.
If
we want to travel down the route of looking for something that we deem
offensive, overlooking the more constructive aspect of individual effort
to bring harmony in a world full of conflicts, the most the Pope may be
accused of may not be of serious dereliction of his duty as the
representative of the pacifist ideology of the teachings of the Christ,
but for not paying �especial� attention to the needs and
hypersensitivity of the Moslem world whose several million people believe
that their world is under constant attack by a formidable
adversary�Western Civilization. At any rate, Moslem leaders should be
more concerned with far more serious problems in Arab countries of social
injustice, poverty in the middle of prosperity of the few, fair
distribution of national wealth, political and individual rights,
education, development, and the threat of some Western leaders et cetera
than make a mountain out of little academic oriented speech by a Pope
whose Church has a record of long standing support of the Palestinian
cause and against the harshness of the national policies against Arabs by
powerful Western nations.
The
harm I see to Moslems around the world and to Arabs and Palestinians in
particular is not to be found in the speech of the Pope, but in the
tantrum displayed by several Moslem politicians and religious leaders in
their campaign speeches and prayer meetings. Moslems must not forget the
fact that the
Vatican
has been constantly criticizing Western leaders, thereby tempering their
aggressiveness, and pointing out the inequities against Palestinians and
Arabs in general. For example, one of the
Vatican
�s most recent criticisms is the activities of the United States
Government in
Iraq
. Attacking Pope Benedict for such minor speech is like attacking the
Catholic Church and the Catholic people all over the world because of the
way the statements were framed by some Moslem political and religious
leaders. Even if the Pope�s speech was blatantly anti-Moslems, one must
weigh the content of such criticism or response carefully, so that in an
effort to criticize one does not descend to making another form of
hate-speech and agitate warmongering.
The
right approach when one is confronted with offensive anti-Moslem
statements, even like those of Pat Robertson (an individual totally
different from the Pope), is not an-eye-for-an-eye response of demonizing
the author of such material nor inflaming the faithful to rise-up in arms
and do harm to innocent people, but to correct the errors of such
individuals calmly. It seems to me that people will benefit greatly from
respectful corrections than from burning effigies of such �offending�
authors, or release edicts to murder such offending authors. Those who
tamper with freedom of thought and expression would sooner than later find
themselves as victims caught in their own web of oppression. Just reading
the Pope�s wonderful speech, I could not help feeling that
Vatican
�s gain is Academia�s
lose of a great philosophy teacher. In
order to have a full understanding of the controversy, it is a good idea
to read what exactly Pope Benedict stated in his speech. It is included
here under. TH _________________________
The
Speech Given by Pope Benedict
XVI at the University of
Regensburg
,
Germany
, on 12 September 2006.
Your
Eminences, Your Magnificences, Your Excellencies, Distinguished Ladies and
Gentlemen,
It
is a moving experience for me to be back again in the university and to be
able once again to give a lecture at this podium. I think back to those
years when, after a pleasant period at the Freisinger Hochschule, I began
teaching at the
University
of
Bonn
. That was in 1959, in the days of the old university made up of ordinary
professors. The various chairs had neither assistants nor secretaries, but
in recompense there was much direct contact with students and in
particular among the professors themselves. We would meet before and after
lessons in the rooms of the teaching staff. There was a lively exchange
with historians, philosophers, philologists and, naturally, between the
two theological faculties. Once a semester there was a dies
academicus, when professors from every faculty appeared before
the students of the entire university, making possible a genuine
experience of universitas - something that you
too, Magnificent Rector, just mentioned - the experience, in other words,
of the fact that despite our specializations which at times make it
difficult to communicate with each other, we made up a whole, working in
everything on the basis of a single rationality with its various aspects
and sharing responsibility for the right use of reason - this reality
became a lived experience. The university was also very proud of its two
theological faculties. It was clear that, by inquiring about the
reasonableness of faith, they too carried out a work which is necessarily
part of the "whole" of the universitas
scientiarum, even if not everyone could share the faith which
theologians seek to correlate with reason as a whole. This profound sense
of coherence within the universe of reason was not troubled, even when it
was once reported that a colleague had said there was something odd about
our university: it had two faculties devoted to something that did not
exist: God. That even in the face of such radical skepticism it is still
necessary and reasonable to raise the question of God through the use of
reason, and to do so in the context of the tradition of the Christian
faith: this, within the university as a whole, was accepted without
question.
I
was reminded of all this recently, when I read the edition by Professor
Theodore Khoury (M�nster) of part of the dialogue carried on - perhaps in
1391 in the winter barracks near Ankara - by the erudite Byzantine emperor
Manuel II Paleologus and an educated Persian on the subject of
Christianity and Islam, and the truth of both. It was presumably the
emperor himself who set down this dialogue, during the siege of
Constantinople
between 1394 and 1402; and this would explain why his arguments are given
in greater detail than those of his Persian interlocutor. The dialogue
ranges widely over the structures of faith contained in the Bible and in
the Qur'an, and deals especially with the image of God and of man, while
necessarily returning repeatedly to the relationship between - as they
were called - three "Laws" or "rules of life": the Old
Testament, the New Testament and the Qur'an. It is not my intention to
discuss this question in the present lecture; here I would like to discuss
only one point - itself rather marginal to the dialogue as a whole -
which, in the context of the issue of "faith and reason", I
found interesting and which can serve as the starting-point for my
reflections on this issue.
In
the seventh conversation (*4V8,>4H - controversy) edited by Professor
Khoury, the emperor touches on the theme of the holy war. The emperor must
have known that surah 2, 256 reads: "There is no compulsion in
religion". According to the experts, this is one of the suras of the
early period, when Mohammed was still powerless and under threat. But
naturally the emperor also knew the instructions, developed later and
recorded in the Qur'an, concerning holy war. Without descending to
details, such as the difference in treatment accorded to those who have
the "Book" and the "infidels", he addresses his
interlocutor with a startling brusqueness on the central question about
the relationship between religion and violence in general, saying:
"Show me just what Mohammed brought that was new, and there you will
find things only evil and inhuman, such as his command to spread by the
sword the faith he preached". The emperor, after having expressed
himself so forcefully, goes on to explain in detail the reasons why
spreading the faith through violence is something unreasonable. Violence
is incompatible with the nature of God and the nature of the soul.
"God", he says, "is not pleased by blood - and not acting
reasonably (F�< 8`(T) is contrary to God's nature. Faith is born of
the soul, not the body. Whoever would lead someone to faith needs the
ability to speak well and to reason properly, without violence and
threats... To convince a reasonable soul, one does not need a strong arm,
or weapons of any kind, or any other means of threatening a person with
death...".
The
decisive statement in this argument against violent conversion is this:
not to act in accordance with reason is contrary to God's nature. The
editor, Theodore Khoury, observes: For the emperor, as a Byzantine shaped
by Greek philosophy, this statement is self-evident. But for Muslim
teaching, God is absolutely transcendent. His will is not bound up with
any of our categories, even that of rationality. Here Khoury quotes a work
of the noted French Islamist R. Arnaldez, who points out that Ibn Hazn
went so far as to state that God is not bound even by his own word, and
that nothing would oblige him to reveal the truth to us. Were it God's
will, we would even have to practice idolatry.
At
this point, as far as understanding of God and thus the concrete practice
of religion is concerned, we are faced with an unavoidable dilemma. Is the
conviction that acting unreasonably contradicts God's nature merely a
Greek idea, or is it always and intrinsically true? I believe that here we
can see the profound harmony between what is Greek in the best sense of
the word and the biblical understanding of faith in God. Modifying the
first verse of the Book of Genesis, the first verse of the whole Bible,
John began the prologue of his Gospel with the words: "In the
beginning was the 8`(@H". This is the very word used by the emperor:
God acts, F�< 8`(T, with logos. Logos means both reason and word - a
reason which is creative and capable of self-communication, precisely as
reason. John thus spoke the final word on the biblical concept of God, and
in this word all the often toilsome and tortuous threads of biblical faith
find their culmination and synthesis. In the beginning was the logos, and
the logos is God, says the Evangelist. The encounter between the Biblical
message and Greek thought did not happen by chance. The vision of
Saint Paul
, who saw the roads to Asia barred and in a dream saw a Macedonian man
plead with him: "Come over to
Macedonia
and help us!" (cf. Acts 16:6-10) - this vision can be interpreted as
a "distillation" of the intrinsic necessity of a rapprochement
between Biblical faith and Greek inquiry.
In
point of fact, this rapprochement had been going on for some time. The
mysterious name of God, revealed from the burning bush, a name which
separates this God from all other divinities with their many names and
simply declares "I am", already presents a challenge to the
notion of myth, to which Socrates' attempt to vanquish and transcend myth
stands in close analogy. Within the Old Testament, the process which
started at the burning bush came to new maturity at the time of the Exile,
when the God of Israel, an Israel now deprived of its land and worship,
was proclaimed as the God of heaven and earth and described in a simple
formula which echoes the words uttered at the burning bush: "I
am". This new understanding of God is accompanied by a kind of
enlightenment, which finds stark expression in the mockery of gods who are
merely the work of human hands (cf. Ps 115). Thus, despite the bitter
conflict with those Hellenistic rulers who sought to accommodate it
forcibly to the customs and idolatrous cult of the Greeks, biblical faith,
in the Hellenistic period, encountered the best of Greek thought at a deep
level, resulting in a mutual enrichment evident especially in the later
wisdom literature. Today we know that the Greek translation of the Old
Testament produced at Alexandria - the Septuagint - is more than a simple
(and in that sense really less than satisfactory) translation of the
Hebrew text: it is an independent textual witness and a distinct and
important step in the history of revelation, one which brought about this
encounter in a way that was decisive for the birth and spread of
Christianity. A profound encounter of faith and reason is taking place
here, an encounter between genuine enlightenment and religion. From the
very heart of Christian faith and, at the same time, the heart of Greek
thought now joined to faith, Manuel II was able to say: Not to act
"with logos" is contrary to God's nature.
In
all honesty, one must observe that in the late Middle Ages we find trends
in theology which would sunder this synthesis between the Greek spirit and
the Christian spirit. In contrast with the so-called intellectualism of
Augustine and Thomas, there arose with Duns Scotus a voluntarism which, in
its later developments, led to the claim that we can only know God's
voluntas ordinata. Beyond this is the realm of God's freedom, in virtue of
which he could have done the opposite of everything he has actually done.
This gives rise to positions which clearly approach those of Ibn Hazn and
might even lead to the image of a capricious God, who is not even bound to
truth and goodness. God's transcendence and otherness are so exalted that
our reason, our sense of the true and good, are no longer an authentic
mirror of God, whose deepest possibilities remain eternally unattainable
and hidden behind his actual decisions. As opposed to this, the faith of
the Church has always insisted that between God and us, between his
eternal Creator Spirit and our created reason, there exists a real
analogy, in which - as the Fourth Lateran Council in 1215 stated -
unlikeness remains infinitely greater than likeness, yet not to the point
of abolishing analogy and its language. God does not become more divine
when we push him away from us in a sheer, impenetrable voluntarism;
rather, the truly divine God is the God who has revealed himself as logos
and, as logos, has acted and continues to act lovingly on our behalf.
Certainly, love, as Saint Paul says, "transcends" knowledge and
is thereby capable of perceiving more than thought alone (cf. Eph 3:19);
nonetheless it continues to be love of the God who is Logos. Consequently,
Christian worship is, again to quote Paul - "8@(46�
8"JD,\"", worship in harmony with the eternal Word and with
our reason (cf. Rom 12:1).
This
inner rapprochement between Biblical faith and Greek philosophical inquiry
was an event of decisive importance not only from the standpoint of the
history of religions, but also from that of world history - it is an event
which concerns us even today. Given this convergence, it is not surprising
that Christianity, despite its origins and some significant developments
in the East, finally took on its historically decisive character in
Europe
. We can also express this the other way around: this convergence, with
the subsequent addition of the Roman heritage, created Europe and remains
the foundation of what can rightly be called Europe.
The
thesis that the critically purified Greek heritage forms an integral part
of Christian faith has been countered by the call for a dehellenization of
Christianity - a call which has more and more dominated theological
discussions since the beginning of the modern age. Viewed more closely,
three stages can be observed in the programme of dehellenization: although
interconnected, they are clearly distinct from one another in their
motivations and objectives.
Dehellenization
first emerges in connection with the postulates of the Reformation in the
sixteenth century. Looking at the tradition of scholastic theology, the
Reformers thought they were confronted with a faith system totally
conditioned by philosophy, that is to say an articulation of the faith
based on an alien system of thought. As a result, faith no longer appeared
as a living historical Word but as one element of an overarching
philosophical system. The principle of sola scriptura, on the other hand,
sought faith in its pure, primordial form, as originally found in the
biblical Word. Metaphysics appeared as a premise derived from another
source, from which faith had to be liberated in order to become once more
fully itself. When Kant stated that he needed to set thinking aside in
order to make room for faith, he carried this programme forward with a
radicalism that the Reformers could never have foreseen. He thus anchored
faith exclusively in practical reason, denying it access to reality as a
whole.
The
liberal theology of the nineteenth and twentieth centuries ushered in a
second stage in the process of dehellenization, with Adolf von Harnack as
its outstanding representative. When I was a student, and in the early
years of my teaching, this programme was highly influential in Catholic
theology too. It took as its point of departure Pascal's distinction
between the God of the philosophers and the God of Abraham, Isaac and
Jacob. In my inaugural lecture at
Bonn
in 1959, I tried to address the issue, and I do not intend to repeat here
what I said on that occasion, but I would like to describe at least
briefly what was new about this second stage of dehellenization. Harnack's
central idea was to return simply to the man Jesus and to his simple
message, underneath the accretions of theology and indeed of hellenization:
this simple message was seen as the culmination of the religious
development of humanity. Jesus was said to have put an end to worship in
favour of morality. In the end he was presented as the father of a
humanitarian moral message. Fundamentally, Harnack's goal was to bring
Christianity back into harmony with modern reason, liberating it, that is
to say, from seemingly philosophical and theological elements, such as
faith in Christ's divinity and the triune God. In this sense,
historical-critical exegesis of the New Testament, as he saw it, restored
to theology its place within the university: theology, for Harnack, is
something essentially historical and therefore strictly scientific. What
it is able to say critically about Jesus is, so to speak, an expression of
practical reason and consequently it can take its rightful place within
the university. Behind this thinking lies the modern self-limitation of
reason, classically expressed in Kant's "Critiques", but in the
meantime further radicalized by the impact of the natural sciences. This
modern concept of reason is based, to put it briefly, on a synthesis
between Platonism (Cartesianism) and empiricism, a synthesis confirmed by
the success of technology. On the one hand it presupposes the mathematical
structure of matter, its intrinsic rationality, which makes it possible to
understand how matter works and use it efficiently: this basic premise is,
so to speak, the Platonic element in the modern understanding of nature.
On the other hand, there is nature's capacity to be exploited for our
purposes, and here only the possibility of verification or falsification
through experimentation can yield ultimate certainty. The weight between
the two poles can, depending on the circumstances, shift from one side to
the other. As strongly positivistic a thinker as J. Monod has declared
himself a convinced Platonist/Cartesian.
This
gives rise to two principles which are crucial for the issue we have
raised. First, only the kind of certainty resulting from the interplay of
mathematical and empirical elements can be considered scientific. Anything
that would claim to be science must be measured against this criterion.
Hence the human sciences, such as history, psychology, sociology and
philosophy, attempt to conform themselves to this canon of scientificity.
A second point, which is important for our reflections, is that by its
very nature this method excludes the question of God, making it appear an
unscientific or pre-scientific question. Consequently, we are faced with a
reduction of the radius of science and reason, one which needs to be
questioned.
I
will return to this problem later. In the meantime, it must be observed
that from this standpoint any attempt to maintain theology's claim to be
"scientific" would end up reducing Christianity to a mere
fragment of its former self. But we must say more: if science as a whole
is this and this alone, then it is man himself who ends up being reduced,
for the specifically human questions about our origin and destiny, the
questions raised by religion and ethics, then have no place within the
purview of collective reason as defined by "science", so
understood, and must thus be relegated to the realm of the subjective. The
subject then decides, on the basis of his experiences, what he considers
tenable in matters of religion, and the subjective "conscience"
becomes the sole arbiter of what is ethical. In this way, though, ethics
and religion lose their power to create a community and become a
completely personal matter. This is a dangerous state of affairs for
humanity, as we see from the disturbing pathologies of religion and reason
which necessarily erupt when reason is so reduced that questions of
religion and ethics no longer concern it. Attempts to construct an ethic
from the rules of evolution or from psychology and sociology, end up being
simply inadequate.
Before
I draw the conclusions to which all this has been leading, I must briefly
refer to the third stage of dehellenization, which is now in progress. In
the light of our experience with cultural pluralism, it is often said
nowadays that the synthesis with Hellenism achieved in the early Church
was a preliminary enculturation which ought not to be binding on other
cultures. The latter are said to have the right to return to the simple
message of the New Testament prior to that enculturation, in order to
acculturate it anew in their own particular milieu. This thesis is not
only false; it is coarse and lacking in precision. The New Testament was
written in Greek and bears the imprint of the Greek spirit, which had
already come to maturity as the Old Testament developed. True, there are
elements in the evolution of the early Church which do not have to be
integrated into all cultures. Nonetheless, the fundamental decisions made
about the relationship between faith and the use of human reason are part
of the faith itself; they are developments consonant with the nature of
faith itself.
And
so I come to my conclusion. This attempt, painted with broad strokes, at a
critique of modern reason from within has nothing to do with putting the
clock back to the time before the Enlightenment and rejecting the insights
of the modern age. The positive aspects of modernity are to be
acknowledged unreservedly: we are all grateful for the marvelous
possibilities that it has opened up for mankind and for the progress in
humanity that has been granted to us. The scientific ethos, moreover, is -
as you yourself mentioned, Magnificent Rector - the will to be obedient to
the truth, and, as such, it embodies an attitude which belongs to the
essential decisions of the Christian spirit. The intention here is not one
of retrenchment or negative criticism, but of broadening our concept of
reason and its application. While we rejoice in the new possibilities open
to humanity, we also see the dangers arising from these possibilities and
we must ask ourselves how we can overcome them. We will succeed in doing
so only if reason and faith come together in a new way, if we overcome the
self-imposed limitation of reason to the empirically verifiable, and if we
once more disclose its vast horizons. In this sense theology rightly
belongs in the university and within the wide-ranging dialogue of
sciences, not merely as a historical discipline and one of the human
sciences, but precisely as theology, as inquiry into the rationality of
faith.
Only
thus do we become capable of that genuine dialogue of cultures and
religions so urgently needed today. In the Western world it is widely held
that only positivistic reason and the forms of philosophy based on it are
universally valid. Yet the world's profoundly religious cultures see this
exclusion of the divine from the universality of reason as an attack on
their most profound convictions. A reason which is deaf to the divine and
which relegates religion into the realm of subcultures is incapable of
entering into the dialogue of cultures. At the same time, as I have
attempted to show, modern scientific reason with its intrinsically
Platonic element bears within itself a question which points beyond itself
and beyond the possibilities of its methodology. Modern scientific reason
quite simply has to accept the rational structure of matter and the
correspondence between our spirit and the prevailing rational structures
of nature as a given, on which its methodology has to be based. Yet the
question why this has to be so is a real question, and one which has to be
remanded by the natural sciences to other modes and planes of thought - to
philosophy and theology.
For
philosophy and, albeit in a different way, for theology, listening to the
great experiences and insights of the religious traditions of humanity,
and those of the Christian faith in particular, is a source of knowledge,
and to ignore it would be an unacceptable restriction of our listening and
responding. Here I am reminded of something Socrates said to Phaedo. In
their earlier conversations, many false philosophical opinions had been
raised, and so Socrates says: "It would be easily understandable if
someone became so annoyed at all these false notions that for the rest of
his life he despised and mocked all talk about being - but in this way he
would be deprived of the truth of existence and would suffer a great
loss". The West has long been endangered by this aversion to the
questions which underlie its rationality, and can only suffer great harm
thereby. The courage to engage the whole breadth of reason, and not the
denial of its grandeur - this is the programme with which a theology
grounded in Biblical faith enters into the debates of our time. "Not
to act reasonably, not to act with logos, is contrary to the nature of
God", said Manuel II, according to his Christian understanding of
God, in response to his Persian interlocutor. It is to this great logos,
to this breadth of reason, that we invite our partners in the dialogue of
cultures. To rediscover it constantly is the great task of the university.
***
NOTE
FROM
VATICAN
:
The
Holy Father intends to supply a subsequent version of this text, complete
with footnotes. The present text must therefore be considered provisional.
|